Lex Fridman Podcast - #325 – Michael Levin: Biology, Life, Aliens, Evolution, Embryogenesis & Xenobots
Episode Date: October 1, 2022Michael Levin is a biologist at Tufts University working on novel ways to understand and control complex pattern formation in biological systems. Please support this podcast by checking out our sponso...rs: - Henson Shaving: https://hensonshaving.com/lex and use code LEX to get 100 free blades with your razor - Eight Sleep: https://www.eightsleep.com/lex to get special savings - LMNT: https://drinkLMNT.com/lex to get free sample pack - InsideTracker: https://insidetracker.com/lex to get 20% off EPISODE LINKS: Michael's Twitter: https://twitter.com/drmichaellevin Michael's Website: https://drmichaellevin.org Michael's Papers: Biological Robots: https://arxiv.org/abs/2207.00880 Synthetic Organisms: https://tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/19420889.2021.2005863 Limb Regeneration: https://science.org/doi/10.1126/sciadv.abj2164 PODCAST INFO: Podcast website: https://lexfridman.com/podcast Apple Podcasts: https://apple.co/2lwqZIr Spotify: https://spoti.fi/2nEwCF8 RSS: https://lexfridman.com/feed/podcast/ YouTube Full Episodes: https://youtube.com/lexfridman YouTube Clips: https://youtube.com/lexclips SUPPORT & CONNECT: - Check out the sponsors above, it's the best way to support this podcast - Support on Patreon: https://www.patreon.com/lexfridman - Twitter: https://twitter.com/lexfridman - Instagram: https://www.instagram.com/lexfridman - LinkedIn: https://www.linkedin.com/in/lexfridman - Facebook: https://www.facebook.com/lexfridman - Medium: https://medium.com/@lexfridman OUTLINE: Here's the timestamps for the episode. On some podcast players you should be able to click the timestamp to jump to that time. (00:00) - Introduction (06:40) - Embryogenesis (14:08) - Xenobots: biological robots (27:55) - Sense of self (37:27) - Multi-scale competency architecture (48:58) - Free will (58:27) - Bioelectricity (1:11:44) - Planaria (1:23:33) - Building xenobots (1:47:08) - Unconventional cognition (2:11:39) - Origin of evolution (2:18:42) - Synthetic organisms (2:25:27) - Regenerative medicine (2:29:14) - Cancer suppression (2:33:15) - Viruses (2:38:28) - Cognitive light cones (2:43:03) - Advice for young people (2:47:47) - Death (2:57:17) - Meaning of life
Transcript
Discussion (0)
The following is a conversation with Michael Levin, one of the most fascinating and brilliant
biologists I've ever talked to.
He and his lab at Tufts University works on novel ways to understand and control complex
pattern formation in biological systems.
Andra Karpathi, a world class AI researcher, is the person who first introduced me to
Michael Levin's work.
I bring this up because these two people
make me realize that biology has a lot to teach us about AI and AI might have a lot to
teach us about biology.
And now a quick few second mention of eSponsor. Check them out in the description. It's the
best way to support this podcast. We got Hansen shaving for a great razor and shave,
eight sleep for e-commerce,
element for on-the-go electrolytes,
and inside tracker for biological tracking,
choose wise and my friends.
And now onto the full batteries,
never add in the middle,
little suck, I try to make these ads here interesting.
So they're worth listening to perhaps mostly because a lot of them don't have anything to do with a sponsor. They're
almost like inspired by the sponsor. But if you still must skip, please check out the
sponsors. They're the reason I'm able to do this podcast. So please support them in
any way you can. I enjoy their stuff, maybe you will too.
This show is brought to you by Hansen Shaving,
a family-owned aerospace manufacturer
bringing precision engineering to your shaving experience.
You had me at engineering.
If there's any word, a person can state to me
that, you know, I was going to say it turns
me on a little bit, but that will be very inappropriate to do in ad reads.
I would never say the thing like that.
But anyway, I find engineering just in all of its forms, materials, engineering, mechanical
engineering, civil engineering, all of it.
I love it. They're using aerospace grade CNC machines and because of that, I'm able to make metal
razors that extend just 0.0013 inches, which is less than the thickness of a human hair.
And the precision of it is the reason you can have a safe, clean, smooth shave.
Check them out at hensonshaving.com slash Lex to pick your razor and use cold Lex and
you'll get 100 free blaze with your razor.
You must add both the 100 blade pack and the razor for the discount to apply.
This episode is also brought to you by 8th Sleep and its new pod 3 mattress.
It is a source of happiness for me.
NEPs bring joy to my heart.
They put to rest all the anxiety, the uncertainty, the sadness, the melancholy that I have on my heart,
to let that fade, and the phoenix rises
from the ashes of the nap.
And a cool surface of the bed with a warm blanket.
I just love it.
It's usually gonna be about 20 to 30 minute nap.
Cures all ills.
I can have so much uncertainty, so much fear,
so much anxiety about the world,
and just
a little nap or insecurity.
All of it, an app can cure it.
Maybe that's a gift, maybe that's a chemical gift for me.
I'm so fortunate not to suffer from sort of chemical depression that can hold you down
for many days, weeks or months. For me, an app can cure
so much and it's beautiful and it's sleep is so so important. So I highly recommend
8 sleep. It's been like I said, a source of a lot of happiness for me. Check it out
and get special savings when you go to 8sleep.com slash Lex.
This episode is also brought to you by Element Electric Light Drink Mix spelled L-M-N-T.
I like their watermelon salt one, but lately I've also been consuming some of the chocolate
mint.
I have a question mark on that.
I don't remember if that's what that is, but it's what it tastes like, and it's delicious,
but it's a different, it's a kind of a different thing.
Intritionally it's the same thing, but spiritually it's a different, it's a kind of a different thing. Intritionally it's the same thing,
but spiritually it's a different thing.
So watermelon salt is more what I'm just trying to add
a little like kick to my water, right?
And making sure I'm getting all the sodium potassium
magnesium right for the low carb stuff I'm doing.
But the chocolate one has a little,
I don't wanna say sweetness, but a little more complex
feeling in the way chocolate does, right?
And so I feel like it's the thing that relaxes me a bit more.
It's like a dessert at the end of the day.
Anyway, get a simple pack for free with any purchase.
Try it at drinkelement.com slash lex.
This show is also brought to you by Inside Tracker, a service I use to track the biological
data for my body.
They have a bunch of plans, most include a blood test that gives you a bunch of information
that is then used by machine learning algorithms to use your blood data, DNA data, and fitness
tracker data to make recommendations for positive diet and lifestyle changes. Your body,
as John Mayer has once said, is a wonderland. It's full of data. It's full of signals that
it's sending to you. And the incredible aspect of our bodies
that is able to integrate those signals
to then maintain health, right?
Now, we're creating a lot of medical tools
and diet tools and all that kind of stuff
that's able to extend the capabilities of our body,
but it needs to know about those signals.
It needs to know about the signals the body sends though.
It's obvious to me that this is the future of health and medicine and all that kind of stuff.
Get special savings for a limited time when you go to insidetracker.com slash Lex.
This is Alex Friedman podcast.
To support it, please check out our sponsors in the description.
And now dear friends, here's Michael Levin. Music
Embryogenesis is the process of building the human body from a single cell. I think it's one of the most incredible things that exists on Earth from a single embryo.
So how does this process work?
Yeah, it is an incredible process.
I think it's maybe the most magical process there is.
And I think one of the most fundamentally interesting things about it is that it shows that
each of us takes the journey from so-called
just physics to mind, right? Because we all start life as a single quiescent unfertilized
oocyte, and it's basically a bag of chemicals, and you look at that and you say, okay, this
is chemistry and physics, and then nine months and some years later, you have an organism with
high level cognition and preferences and an inner life, and so on. And what embryogenesis tells us is that that transformation
from physics to mind is gradual.
It's smooth.
There is no special place where the lightning bolt says,
boom, now you've gone from physics to true cognition.
That doesn't happen.
And so we can see in this process that the whole mystery,
the biggest mystery of the universe, basically,
how you get mind from matter.
From just physics, in quotes. Yeah from matter. From just physics and quotes.
Yeah.
So where's the magic into the thing?
How do we get from information code in DNA
and make physical reality out of that information?
So one of the things that I think is really important
if we're gonna bring in DNA into this picture
is to think about the fact that what DNA encodes
is the hardware of life. DNA contains
the instructions for the kind of micro level hardware that every cell gets to play with. So all the
proteins, all the signaling factors, the ion channels, all the cool little pieces of hardware that
cells have. That's what's in the DNA. The rest of it is in so-called generic laws and these are
laws of mathematics, these are laws of computation, these are laws of physics,
of all kinds of interesting things
that are not directly in the DNA.
And that process, I think the reason I always put
just physics in quotes is because I don't think
there is such a thing as just physics.
I think that thinking about these things
in binary categories, like this is physics,
this is true cognition, this is as if it's only faking,
these kinds of things.
I think that's what gets us in trouble.
I think that we really have to understand that it's a continuum.
We have to work up the scaling, the laws of scaling.
We can certainly talk about that.
There's a lot of really interesting thoughts to be had there.
The physics is deeply integrated with the information.
The DNA doesn't exist in its own. The DNA is integrated
as in some sense in response to the laws of physics at every scale. The laws of the environment
exists in.
Yeah, the environment and also the laws of the universe. I mean, the thing about the
thing about the DNA is that it's once evolution discovers a certain kind of machine that
if the physical implementation is appropriate
it's sort of, and this is hard to talk about because we don't have a good vocabulary for
this yet, but it's a very kind of platonic notion that if the machine is there, it pulls
down interesting things that you do not have to evolve from scratch because the laws of
physics give it to you for free.
So just as a really stupid example, if you're trying to evolve a particular triangle, you
can evolve the first angle and you evolve the second angle.
But you don't need to evolve the third.
You know what it is already.
Now, why do you know that's a gift for free from geometry in a particular space?
You know what that angle has to be.
And if you evolve an ion channel, which is ion channels are basically transistors, right?
They're voltage gated current conductances.
If you evolve that ion channel, you immediately get to use things
like truth tables. You get logic functions. You don't have to evolve the logic
function. You don't have to evolve a truth table. It doesn't have to be in the DNA.
You get it for free, right? And the fact that if you have an end gate, you can
build anything you want. You get that for free. All you have to evolve is that
that first step, that first little machine that enables you to couple to those
laws. And there's laws of adhesion and many other things. And this is all that interplay between the
hardware that's set up by the genetics and the software that's based, right? The physiological
software that basically does all the computation and the cognition and everything else
is a real interplay between the information and the DNA and the laws of physics of computation and so on. So is it fair to say just like this idea that the laws of mathematics are discovered,
they're latent within the fabric of the universe in that same way the laws of biology are kind of
discovered. Yeah, I think that's absolutely and it's probably not a popular view but I think
that's right on the money. Yeah, well I think that's a really deep idea. Then embryogenesis is the process of revealing, of embodying, of manifesting these laws.
You're not building the laws.
You're just creating the capacity to reveal.
Yes.
I think, again, not the standard view of molecular biology by any means, but I think that's
right on the money.
I'll give you a simple example.
Some of our latest work with these xenobots, right?
So what we've done is to take some skin cells off of an early frog embryo and basically
ask about their plasticity.
If we give you a chance to sort of reboot your multicellularity in a different context,
what would you do?
Because what you might assume by the thing about embryogenesis is that it's super reliable, right? It's very robust. And that really obscures some of its most
interesting features. We get used to it. We get used to the fact that acorns make oak
trees and frog eggs make frogs. And we say, well, what else is it going to make? That's
what it, you know, that's what it makes. That's a standard story. But the reality is, and
so you look at these at these skin cells and you say, well, what do they know how to do? Well, they know how to be a passive-boring, two-dimensional outer layer keeping the bacteria
from getting into the embryo. That's what they know how to do. Well, it turns out that
if you take these skin cells and you remove the rest of the embryo, so you remove all of
the rest of the cells and you say, well, you're by yourself now, what do you want to do?
So what they do is they form this little, this multi-little creature
that runs around the dish. They have all kinds of incredible capacities. They navigate through
mazes. They have various behaviors that they do both independently and together. They,
they have a, basically they implement von Neumann's dream of self-replication because if you
sprinkle a bunch of loose cells into the dish, what they do is they run around, they collect those
cells into little piles. They sort of mush them together until those little piles become the next generation
of xenobots. So you've got this machine that builds copies of itself from loose material in its
environment. None of this are things that you would have expected from the frog genome. In fact,
there's a wild type, the genome is wild type, there's nothing wrong with their genetics, nothing
has been added, no nanomaterials, no genomic editing, nothing.
And so what we have done there is engineered by subtraction, what you've done is you've
removed the other cells that normally basically bully these cells into being skin cells.
And you find out that what they really want to do is to be this, they're default behaviors
to be a xenobot.
But in vivo, in the embryo, they get told to be skinned by these other cell types.
So now here comes this really interesting question that you just posed.
When you ask, where does the form of the tappel and the frog come from, the standard answer
is, well, it's selection.
So over millions of years, it's been shaped to produce this specific body with that's fit
for froggy environments.
Where does the shape of the xenobot come from?
There's never been any xenobots. There's never been selection to be a good xenobot.
These cells find themselves in the new environment in 48 hours.
They figure out how to be an entirely different proto organism with new capacities
like kinematic cell replication. That's not how frogs or tadpoles replicate.
We've made it impossible for them to replicate their normal way
within a couple days these guys find a new way of doing it. That's not done anywhere
else in the biosphere. Well, actually, let's step back and define what are xenobots.
So a xenobot is a self-assembling little proto organism. It's also a biological robot. Those things
are not distinct. It's a member of both classes. How much is it biology? How much is it robot?
It's a member of both classes. How much is it biology?
How much is it robot?
At this point, most of it is biology,
because what we're doing is we're discovering
natural behaviors of the cells and also of the cell
collectives.
That one of the really important parts of this
was that we're working together with Josh Bongart's
group at University of Vermont.
Their computer scientists do AI, and they've basically been
able to use an evolutionary, simulated evolution approach to ask, how can we manipulate these
cells, give them signals, not rewire their DNA, so not hardware, but experience signals.
So can we remove some cells, can we add some cells, can we poke them in different ways,
to get them to do other things.
So in the future, there's going to be, you know, we're now, and this is future on publish
work, but we're doing all sorts of interesting ways to reprogram
them to new behaviors. But before you can start to reprogram these things, you have to
understand what their innate capacities are.
Okay. So that means engineering programming, engineering them in the future. And in some
sense, the definition of a robot is something you in part engineer.
Yeah, and first of all, I mean, it's such a fuzzy definition anyway.
In some sense, many of the organisms with the nirbody are kinds of robots.
Yes, yes.
And I think robots is a weird line because we tend to see robots as the other.
I think there will be a time in the future
when there's going to be something
that can't do the civil rights movements for robots,
but we'll talk about that later, perhaps.
Sure.
Anyway, so how do you, can we just linger on it?
How do you build a xenobot?
What are we talking about here?
From when does it start and how does it become the glorious xenobot?
Yeah, so just to take one step back, one of the things that a lot of people get stuck on is they say,
well, you know, engineering requires new DNA circuits or it requires new nanomaterials, you know,
what the thing is we are now moving from old school engineering, which use passive
materials, right, that things, you know, wood metal, things like this, that basically the
only thing you could depend on is that they were going to keep their shape.
That's it.
They don't do anything else.
It's on you as an engineer to make them do everything they're going to do.
And then there are active materials and now computation materials.
This is a whole new era.
These are agential materials.
This is your, you're now collaborating
with your substrate because your material has an
agenda. These cells have billions of years of
evolution, they have goals, they have preferences,
they're not just going to sit where you put them.
That's hilarious that you have to talk your material
and to keep it shape. That is exactly right.
That is exactly right. That is right.
Stay there. It's like getting a bunch of cats or something
and trying to organize a sheep out of them.
It's funny. We're on the same page here because in a paper, this is currently just been accepted
in Nature by Engineering. One of the figures I have is building a tower out of Legos versus dogs.
So think about the difference. If you build out of Legos, you have full control over where it's
going to go. But if somebody knocks it over, it's game over. With the dogs, you cannot just come
and stack them. They're not going to stay that way. But the good news is that if you train
them, then somebody knocks it over, they'll get right back up. So it's all right. So as an
engineer, what you really want to know is, what can I depend on this thing to do? That's
really, a lot of people have definitions of robots as far as what they're made over, how
they got here, you know, design versus evolve, whatever. I don't think any of that is useful.
I think, I think as an engineer, what you want to know is how much can I depend on this thing
to do when I'm not around to micromanage it?
What level of, what level of dependency can I give this thing?
How much agency does it have?
Which then tells you what techniques do you?
So do you use micromanagement?
Like you put everything where it goes?
Do you train it?
Do you give it signals?
Do you try to convince it to do things right?
How much, you know, how intelligent is your substrate? And so now we're moving into this area where you're working with
agential materials. That's a collaboration. That's not old style.
What's the word you're using? Agential? Agential. What does that mean?
Agency. It comes from the word agency. So basically the material has agency, meaning that
it has some level of, obviously not human level, but some level of preferences, goals,
memories, ability to remember things to compute into the future, meaning anticipate.
You know, when you're working with cells, they have all of that to some to various degrees.
Is that empowering or limiting having material as a mind of its own literally?
I think it's both, right?
So it raises difficulties because it means that if you're using the old mindset, which is a linear
kind of extrapolation of what's going to happen, you're going to be surprised and shocked all the time because biology
does not do what we literally expect materials to do. On the other hand, it's massively liberating and so in the following way
I've argued that
advances in regenerative medicine
require us to take advantage
of this because what it means is that you can get the material to do things that you don't know
how to micromanage. So just as a simple example, right, if you had a rat and you wanted this rat to
do a circus trick, put a ball in the little hoop, you can do it the micromanagement way which is
try to control every neuron and try to play the thing like a puppet, right, and maybe someday that'll
be possible, maybe, or you can train the rat.
And this is why humanity for thousands of years before we knew any neuroscience.
We had no idea what's between the ears of any animal.
We were able to train these animals because once you recognize the level of agency of a certain system,
you can use appropriate techniques.
If you know the currency of motivation, reward and punishment, you know how smart it is,
you know, what kinds of things it likes to do.
You are searching a much more, much smoother, much nicer problem space than if you try to
micromanage the thing.
And in regenerative medicine, when you're trying to get, let's say, an arm to grow back
or an eye to repair a cell, birth defect or something, do you really want to be controlling
tens of thousands of genes at each point to try to micromanage it, or do you want to find
the high-level modular controls that say, build an arm here?
You already know how to build an arm, you did it before, do it again.
So I think it's both.
It's both difficult and it challenges us to develop new ways of engineering, and it's
hugely empowering.
Okay, so how do you maybe stick with the metaphor of dogs and cats?
I presume you have to figure out the,
find the dogs and dispose of the cats.
Because it's like the old hurting cats is an issue.
So you may be able to train dogs.
I suspect you will not be able to train cats.
Or if you do, you're never going to be able
to trust them.
So, is there a way to figure out which material is amenable to hurting?
Is it in the lab work or is it in simulation?
Right now it's largely in the lab because our simulations do not capture yet the most interesting
and powerful things about biology.
So the simulation does what we're pretty good at simulating our feed forward emergent
types of things, right?
So cellular automata, if you have simple rules and you sort of roll those forward for every
agent or if you sell in the simulation and complex things happen, you know, ant colony
or algorithms, things like that, we're good at that.
And that's, and that's fine.
The difficulty with all of that is that it's incredibly hard to reverse. So this is a really hard inverse problem. If you look at
a bunch of termites and they make a thing with a single chimney and you say, well, I like it,
but I'd like two chimneys. How do you change the rules of behavior-free termites so they make
two chimneys, right? Or if you say, here are a bunch of cells that are creating this kind of
organism, I don't think that's optimal. I'd like to repair that birth defect.
How do you control all the individual low-level rules, right?
All the protein interactions and everything else.
Rolling it back from the anatomy that you want to the low-level hardware rules is in general
intractable.
It's an inverse problem.
It's generally not solvable.
So, right now, it's mostly in the lab because what we need to do is we need to understand
how biology uses top-down controls
So the idea is not not bottom-up emergence, but the idea of
things like gold directed
Test-operate exit kinds of loops where where it's basically an error minimization function over a new space
There's not a space of gene expression, but for example a space of anatomy
So just as a simple example if you have a salamander
It's got an arm. You can
amputate that arm anywhere along the length. It will grow exactly what's needed and then it stops.
That's the most amazing thing about regeneration is that it stops. It knows when to stop. When does
it stop? It stops when a correct salamander arm has been completed. So that tells you that's a
that means ends kind of analysis where it has to know what the correct limits supposed to look like, right?
So it has a way to ascertain the current shape. It has a way to measure that delta from from what shape it's supposed to be and it will keep taking actions meaning remodeling and growing and everything else until that's complete.
So once you know that and we've taken advantage of this in the lab to do some some really wild things with with both Plenary and Frogambrias and so on.
Once you know that, you can start playing
with that homestatic cycle.
You can ask, for example,
well, how does it remember what the correct shape is
and can we mess with that memory?
Can we give it a false memory of what the shape should be
and let the cells build something else?
Or can we mess with the measurement apparatus, right?
It gives you those kinds of,
so the idea is to basically appropriate a lot of the approaches
and concepts from cognitive neuroscience and behavioral science into things that previously were taken to be dumb materials
and you know you'd get yelled at in class if you for being anthropomorphic, if you said,
well, my cells want to do this and my cells want to do that.
And I think that's a major mistake that leaves a ton of capabilities on the table.
So thinking about biologic systems, those things that have memory, have almost something
like cognitive ability.
But I mean, how incredible is it that the salamander arm is being rebuilt, not with a dictator.
It's kind of like the cellular automata system. All the individual workers are doing their
own thing. So where's that, where we top down signal that does
the control coming from? Like, how can you find it? Yeah. Like,
why does it stop growing? How does it know the shape? How does
it have memory of the shape? And how does it tell everybody to be
like, whoa, whoa, slow down, we're done. So the first thing to think about, I think, is that there are no examples anywhere of
a central dictator because in this kind of science, because everything is made of parts.
And so we, even though we feel as a unified central sort of intelligence and kind of point
of cognition, we are a bag of neurons, right?
We all intelligence is collective intelligence. There's this, this is important to kind of
think about because a lot of people think, okay, there's real intelligence, like me,
and then there's collective intelligence, which is ants and flocks of birds and, you know,
termites and things like that. And, you know, and maybe it's appropriate to think of them as
a, as a, as an individual. And maybe it's
not. And a lot of people are skeptical about that. But you've got to realize that there's
no such thing as this like indivisible diamond of intelligence that's like this one central
thing that's not made of parts. We are all made of parts. And so if you believe that
which I think is hard to get around that we in fact have a centralized set of goals and preferences
and we plan and we do things and so on, you are already committed to the fact that a collection of
cells is able to do this because we are a collection of cells. There's no getting around that.
In our case, what we do is we navigate the three-dimensional world and we have behavior.
This is blowing my mind right now because we are just a collection of cells.
Oh yeah, yeah. When I'm moving this arm,
right now because we are just a collection of cells. Oh yeah, yeah. So when I'm moving this arm,
I feel like I'm the central dictator of that action. But there's a lot of stuff going on. Like, all the cells here are collaborating in some interesting way. They're getting signal from
the central nervous system. Well, even the central nervous system is misleadingly named because
it isn't really central. Again, it's what it's what it's just a bunch of cells. I mean, all of it, right? There are no
you, there are no singular, indivisible intelligences anywhere. We are all every, every example that we've
ever seen is, is a collective of some of something. It's just that we're used to it. We're used to
that, you know, we're used to, okay, this thing is kind of a single thing, but it's really not.
You zoom in, you know what you see, you see a bunch of cells running around,
and so is there some unifying or jumping around, but that's something that you look as the biological
signal versus the biochemical, the chemistry, the electricity, maybe the life isn't that
The chemistry, the electricity, maybe the life isn't that
versus the cells. It's the, there's an orchestra playing and
the resulting music is the dictator.
That's not bad.
Dennis, Dennis Noble's kind of view of things.
He has two really good books where he talks about this musical analogy, right?
So I think that's, I like it. I like it. Is it wrong? I don't think it's no. I don't think it's wrong
I don't I don't think it's wrong. I think I think the important thing about it is that we have to come to grips with the fact that a
True a true proper cognitive intelligence can still be made of parts.
Those things are, and in fact, it has to be.
And I think it's a real shame, but I see this all the time.
When you have a collective, like this, whether it be a group of robots or a collection of cells or neurons or whatever,
as soon as we gain some insight into how it works, right, meaning that,
oh, I see, in order to take you this action, here's the information
that got processed via this chemical mechanism
or whatever, immediately people say,
oh, well, then that's not real cognition,
that's just physics.
And I think this is fundamentally flawed
because if you zoom into anything,
what are you going to see?
Of course, you're just going to see physics.
What else could be underneath, right?
That's not gonna be fairy dust,
it's gonna be physics and chemistry.
But that doesn't take away from the magic of the fact that there are certain ways to arrange
that physics and chemistry and in particular the bioelectricity, which I like a lot,
to give you an emergent collective with goals and preferences and memories and anticipations
that do not belong to any of the subunits. So I think what we're getting into here,
and we can talk about how this happens during embryogenesis and so on, what we're getting into is the origin of the of of a self,
yeah, with a big with a capital S. So we ourselves, there are many other kinds of
selves, and we can tell some really interesting stories about where selves come from and how they
become unified. Yeah, is this the first or at least humans tend to think that this is the level of which the self with the capital
us is first born.
But and we really don't want to see human civilization or earth itself as one living organism.
That's very uncomfortable to us.
It is.
Yeah.
But yeah, where's the self born?
We have to grow up past that.
So what I like to do is, I'll tell you two quick stories,
about that.
I like to roll backwards.
So as opposed to, so if you start and you say,
OK, here's a paramecium and you see it,
it's a single cell organism.
You see it doing various things.
And people will say, OK, I'm sure there's
some chemical story to be told about how it's doing it.
So that's not true cognition, right?
And people will argue about that.
I like to work it backwards.
I say, let's agree that you and I, as we sit here, are examples of true cognition, right? And people will argue about that. I like to work it backwards. I see, let's agree that you and I,
as we sit here, are examples of true cognition
if anything, is if there's anything that's true cognition,
we are examples of it.
Now let's just roll back slowly, right?
So you roll back to the time we were a small child
and used to do in whatever.
And then just sort of day by day,
you roll back and eventually you become
more or less that parent me see them
and then you sort of even below that, right?
As an unfertilized OSI. So, no one has, to my knowledge, no one has come up with any convincing
discrete step at which my cognitive powers disappear, right? It just doesn't, the biology
doesn't offer any specific step. It's incredibly smooth and slow and continuous. And so I think this idea that it just sort of magically shows up at one point and then
humans have true selves that don't exist elsewhere. I think it runs against everything we
know about evolution, everything we know about developmental biology. These are all slow
and continue. And the other really important story I want to tell is where embryos come
from. So think about this for a second. Amniote embryos. So this is humans, birds and so on. Mammals and birds and so on. Imagine a flat disc of cells. So there's maybe
50,000 cells. And in that, so when you get an egg from a fertilized, let's say you buy a fertilized
egg from a farm, right? That, that egg will, will have about 50,000 cells in a flat disk. It looks a little tiny, a little frisbee.
And in that flat disk, what'll happen is there'll be one set
of cells will become special.
And it will tell all the other cells,
I'm going to be the head, you guys don't be the head.
And so it'll amplify symmetry breaking, amplification,
you get one embryo.
There's some neural tissue and some other stuff forms. Now, now you say, okay, I had one egg and one embryo and there you go, what else could
it be? Well, the reality is, and I used to, I did all of this as a grad student, if you take a little
needle and you make a scratch in that blasted room in that, in that disk, such that the cells can't
talk to each other for a while, it heals up, but for a while they can't talk to each other. What'll
happen is that both regions will decide that they can be the embryo, and then
they will be two of them. And then when they heal up, they become conjoined twins, and you can
make two, you can make three, you can make lots. So the question of how many cells are in there
cannot be answered until it's actually played all the way through. It isn't necessarily that
there's just one. There can be many. So what you have is you have this medium, this undifferentiated, I'm sure there's a psychological
version of this somewhere that I don't know the proper terminology, but you have this, you have this
list like, put ocean of potentiality, you have these thousands of cells, and some number of
individuals are going to be formed out of it, usually one, sometimes zero, sometimes several,
formed out of the usually one, sometimes zero, sometimes several.
And they form out of the cells because a region of the cells
organizes into a collective that will have goals,
goals that individual cells don't have, for example,
make a limb, make an eye. How many eyes will exactly to?
So individual cells don't know what an eye is. They don't know how many eyes you're supposed to have, but the collective does.
The collective has goals and memories and anticipations that the individual cells don't. And that, that the establishment of that
boundary with its own ability to, to pursue certain goals, that's the origin of, of selfhood.
But is that goal in there somewhere where they always destined, like, are they discovering that goal?
Like, where the hell did evolution discover this?
When you went from the Prokaryats to your Karyotic cells,
and then they started making groups, and when you make a certain group,
you make a, you make it sound,
and it's such a tricky thing to try to understand.
You make it sound like this cells didn't get together
and came up with a goal,
but the very act of them getting together
reveal the goal that was always there,
there was always that potential for that goal.
So the first thing to say is that
there are way more questions here
than certainties, okay, so everything I'm telling you is cutting edge developing, you know, stuff.
So it's not as if any of us know the answer to this.
But here's my opinion on this.
I think what evolution, I don't think that evolution produces solutions to specific problems.
In other words, specific environments.
Like here's a frog that can live well in a frog environment.
I think what evolution produces is problem-solving
machines that will solve problems in different spaces. So not just three-dimensional space.
This goes back to what we were talking about before. The brain is a evolutionarily a late
development. It's a system that is able to pursue goals in three-dimensional space by giving
commands to muscles where that system comes from. That system evolved from a much more ancient,
evolutionarily much more ancient system,
where collections of cells gave instructions
for cell behaviors, meaning cells moved to divide,
to die, to change into different cell types,
to navigate more for space, the space of anatomies,
the space of all possible anatomies.
And before that, cells were navigating transcriptional space, which is the space of allomies, the space of all possible anatomies. And before that, cells were navigating transcriptional space,
which is a space of all possible gene expressions.
And before that, metabolic space.
So what evolution has done, I think, is produced hardware
that is very good at navigating different spaces
using a bag of tricks, which I'm sure many of them
we can steal for autonomous vehicles and robotics
and various things.
And what happens is that they navigate these spaces
without a whole lot of commitment to what the space is.
In fact, they don't know what the space is.
We are all brains in a vat, so to speak.
Every cell does not know, every cell is some other
cell's external environment.
So where does that border between you and the outside world,
you don't really know where that is. Every collection of cells has to figure that out from scratch.
And the fact that evolution requires all of these things to figure out what they are, what effectors,
they have what sensors, they have where does it make sense to draw a boundary between me and the
outside world. The fact that you have to build all that from scratch, this auto-poises,
is what defines the border of a self. Now biology uses like a multi-scale
competency architecture, meaning that every level has goals. So molecular networks have
goals, cells have goals, tissues, organs, colonies, and it's the interplay of all of those that
enable biology to solve problems in new ways, for example, in xenobots and various other things.
This is, you know, it's exactly, as you said,
in many ways, the cells are discovering new ways of being,
but at the same time, evolution certainly shapes all this.
So evolution is very good at this,
a gentle by engineering, right?
When evolution is discovering a new way of being an animal,
you know, when an animal or a plant or something, sometimes it's by changing the hardware, you know, protein, changing
proteins, protein structure and so on. But much of the time, it's not by changing the hardware,
it's by changing the signals that the cells give to each other. It's doing what we as engineers do,
which is try to convince the cells to do various things by using signals, experiences, stimuli.
That's what biology does. It has to, because it's not dealing with a blank slate. Every time, as you know, if you're a evolution and you're
trying to make a, make an organism, you're not dealing with a passive material that is,
is fresh and you have to specify, it already wants to do certain things. So the easiest
way to do that search to find whatever is going to be adaptive is to find the signals
that are going to convince themselves to do various things, right?
Your sense is that evolution operates both in the software and the hardware and it's
just easier, more efficient operator in the software.
Yes, and I should also say I don't think the distinction is sharp.
In other words, I think it's a continuum, but I think we can, but I think it's a meaningful
distinction where you can make changes to a particular protein
and now the enzymatic function is different and metabolizes differently and whatever and that will have implications for fitness.
Or you can change the huge amount of information in the genome that isn't structural at all.
It's signaling. It's when and how do cells say certain things to each other, and that can have massive changes as far as how it's going to solve problems.
I mean, this idea of multi-heroarchical competence architecture, which is incredible to think
about.
So this hierarchy that evolution builds, I don't know who's responsible for this.
I also see the incompetence of bureaucracies of humans when they get together.
So how the hell does evolution build this?
Where at every level, only the best get to stick around, they somehow figure out how to
do their job without knowing the bigger picture.
And then there's like the bosses that do the bigger thing somehow or that you can now
abstract away the small group of cells as an organ or something.
And then that organ does something bigger in the context of the full body or something
like this.
How is that built?
Is there some intuition you can kind of provide of how that's constructed that hierarchical
competence architecture?
I love that.
Competence, just the word competence.
It's pretty cool in this context because everybody's good at their job somehow.
Yeah.
No, it's really key.
And the other nice thing about competency is that so my central belief in all of this
is that engineering is the right perspective on all of this stuff because it gets you away from subjective terms.
You know, people talk about sentience and this and that.
Those things very hard to define.
People argue about them philosophically.
I think that engineering terms like competency, like, you know, pursuit of goals, right?
All of these things are empirically incredibly useful because you know it when you see it. And if it helps you build, right? All of these things are empirically incredibly useful because you know
it when you see it. And if it helps you build, right? If I can pick the right level, I say,
this thing has, I believe this is x level of like confidence, I think it's like a thermostat,
or I think it's like a better thermostat, or I think it's a, you know, various other kinds of,
you know, there's many, many different kinds of complex systems.
If that helps me to control and and predict and build such systems,
then that's all the risk to say there's no more philosophy to argue about.
So, so I like competency in that way because you can quantify,
you could you have to, in fact, you have to make a client competent at what?
And then, or if I say, if I tell you it has a goal,
the question is what's the goal?
And how do you know?
And I say, well, because every time I deviated from this particular state,
that's what it spends energy to get back to. That's the goal. And we can
quantify it and we can be objective about it. So, so, so the, the, we're not used to thinking
about this. I give a talk sometimes called, why don't robots get cancer, right? And the reason
robots don't get cancer is because, generally speaking, with a few exceptions, our, our architecture
has been, you've got a bunch of dumb parts, and you hope that if you put them together,
the overlying machine will have some intelligence
and do something or other, right?
But the individual parts don't care, they don't have an agenda.
Biology isn't like that.
Every level has an agenda,
and the final outcome is the result of cooperation
and competition both within and across levels.
So for example, during embryogenesis,
your tissues and organs are competing with each other.
And it's actually a really important part of development.
There's a reason they compete with each other.
They're not all just helping each other.
They're also competing for information,
for metabolic, for limited metabolic constraints.
But to get back to your other point,
which is, this seems like really efficient and good, and so on compared to some of our human efforts, we also have to keep
in mind that what happens here is that each level bends the option space for the level
beneath so that your parts, basically, they don't see the, the, the geometry, so I'm, I'm
using, I think, and I think I take this seriously, terminology from like relativity,
right, where the space is literally bent. So the option space is deformed by the higher level,
so that the lower level, so all they really have to do is go down their concentration gradient.
They don't have to, in fact, they don't, they can't know what the big picture is. But if you
bend the space just right, if they do what locally seems right, they end up doing your bidding.
They end up doing things that are optimal
in the higher space.
Conversely, because the components
are good at getting their job done,
you as the higher level don't need to try to compute
all the low level controls.
All you're doing is bending the space.
You don't know or care how they're going to do it.
Give you a super simple example.
And in the TATL, we found that.
Okay, so TAPLs need to become frogs and to go from a TAPL head to a frog head, you have
to rearrange the face.
So the eyes have to move forward, the jaws have to come off the nostrils, move like
everything moves.
It used to be thought that because all TAPLs look the same and all frogs look the same.
If you just remember, if every piece just moves in the right direction, the right amount,
then you get your frog, right? So we decided to test. I had this hypothesis
that I thought, actually, the system is probably more intelligent than that. So what did we
do? We made what we call Picasso tapples. So these are everything is scramble. So the eyes
are on the back of the head. Their jaws are off to the side. Everything is scrambled.
Well, guess what they make? They make pretty normal frogs because all the different things
move around in novel paths, configurations,
until they get to the correct frog, you know, sort of frog face configuration, then they stop.
So, the thing about that is now imagine evolution, right? So, you make some sort of mutation,
and it does, like every mutation, it does many things. So, something good comes of it,
but also it moves your mouth off to the side. Now, if there wasn't this
multi-scale competency, you can see where this is going. If there wasn't this multi-scale
competency, the organism would be dead, your fitness is zero because you can't eat, and
you would never get to explore the other beneficial consequences of that mutation. You'd have
to wait until you find some other way of doing it without moving them out. That's really
hard. So the fitness landscape would be incredibly rugged. Evolution would take forever. The reason it works, and what one of the reasons it works so well, is because
you do that, no worries. The mouse will find its way where it belongs, right? So now
you get to explore. So what that means is that all of these mutations that otherwise would
be deleterious are now neutral, because the competency of the parts make up for all kinds
of things. So all the noise of development, all the variability
in the environment, all these things,
the companies that you have the parts make up for.
So that's all fantastic, right?
That's all great.
The only other thing to remember
when we compare this to human efforts is this.
Every component has its own goals and various spaces,
usually with very little regard for the welfare
of the other levels.
So as a simple example, you know,
you as a complex system, you will go out
and you will do, you know, jujitsu or whatever,
you'll have some go, you have to go rock climbing,
scrape a bunch of cells off your hands,
and then you're happy as a system, right?
You come back and you've accomplished some goals
and you're really happy, those cells are dead, they're gone,
right?
Did you think about those cells?
Not really, right? You had some bruising, out.
Selfish, that's it.
And so that's the thing to remember is that, you know,
and we know this from history, is that just being a collective
isn't enough, because what the goals of that collective
will be relative to the welfare of the individual parts
is a massive, open question.
He ends just to find the means.
I'm telling you, Stalin was onto something.
No, that's the danger.
But we can say exactly.
That's the danger of, for us humans, we have to construct ethical systems under which we
don't take seriously the full mechanism of biology and apply it to the way the world functions,
which is an interesting line we've drawn.
The world that built us is the one we reject in some sense when we construct human societies.
The idea that this country was founded on that all men are created equal. That's such a fascinating idea. That's like you're fighting against nature.
Saying, well, there's something bigger here than a hierarchical competency architecture.
There's so many interesting things you said. So from an algorithmic perspective,
the act of bending the option space,
So from an algorithmic perspective, the act of bending the option space, that's really that's really profound.
Because if you look at the way AI systems are built today, there's a big system, like
I said, with robots, and as a goal, and he gets better and better at optimizing that goal
at accomplishing that goal. But if biology built a hierarchical system where everything is doing computation, and everything
is accomplishing the goal, not only that, it's kind of dumb, you know, with the limited,
with a bent option space, it's just doing the thing that's the easiest thing for it in some sense.
And somehow that allows you to have turtles on top of turtles, literally dumb systems
on top of dumb systems that as a whole creates something incredibly smart.
Yeah, I mean, every system has some degree of intelligence in its own problem domain. So cells will have problems
they're trying to solve in physiological space and transcriptional space. And then I
can give you some cool examples of that. But the collective is trying to solve problems
in anatomical space, right, informing a creature and growing your blood vessels and so on.
And then the whole body is solving yet other problems.
They may be in social space and linguistic space
and three dimensional space.
And who knows, the group might be solving problems
and I don't know some sort of financial space or something.
So one of the major differences with most AI's today
is the kind of flatness of the architecture, but also of the fact that
they are constructed from outside their borders and their, you know, so to a large extent,
and of course there are counter examples now, but to a large extent, our technology has been such that you create a machine or a robot,
it knows what its sensors are, it knows
what its effectors are, it knows the boundary between it and the outside.
Well, all that this is given from the outside.
Biology constructs this from scratch.
Now, the best example of this that originally in robotics was actually Josh Bondgard's
work in 2006 where he made these robots that did not know their shape to start with.
So like a baby, they sort of floundered around, they made some hypotheses, well, I did this
and I moved in this way, well, maybe I'm a,
whatever, maybe I have wheels or maybe I have six legs
or whatever, right?
And they would make a model and eventually a crawl around.
So that's, I mean, that's really good.
That's part of the auto-pulses,
but we can go a step further
and some people are doing this
and then we're sort of working on some of this too,
is this idea that let's even go back further,
you don't even know what sensors you have.
You don't know where you end in the outside world begins.
All you have is certain things like active inference,
meaning you're trying to minimize surprise.
You have some metabolic constraints.
You don't have all the energy you need.
You don't have all the time in the world to think about everything you want to think about.
That means that you can't afford to be a micro reductionist.
All this data coming in, you have to coarse-grained it and say,
I'm gonna take all this stuff and I'm gonna call that a cat.
I'm gonna take all this, I'm gonna call that the edge
of the table I don't wanna fall off of.
And I don't wanna know anything about the micro-states.
What I wanna know is what is the optimal way
to cut up my world?
And by the way, this thing over here, that's me.
And the reason that's me is because I have more control
over this than I have over any of this other stuff.
And so now you can begin to write.
So that's self-construction that figuring out making models of the outside world and
then turning that inwards and starting to make a model of yourself, right?
Which immediately starts to get into issues of agency and control because
in order to if you are under metabolic constraints meaning you don't have the energy,
right, that all the energy in the world you have to be efficient,
that immediately forces you to start telling stories about coarse-grained agents that do things,
right. You don't have the energy to like Laplace's team and you know, calculate every
possible state that's going to happen. You have to coarse-grained and you have to say,
that is the kind of creature that does things either things that I avoid or things that I will go
towards, that's a mate or food or whatever it's going to be.
So right at the base of very simple organisms starting to make models of agents doing things,
that is the origin of models of free will basically, because you see the world around you as
having agency and then you turn that on yourself and you say, wait, I have agency too, I do things. And then you make decisions about what you're
going to do. So all of this, one model is to view all of those kinds of things as being
driven by that early need to determine what you are and to do so and to then take actions
in the most energetically efficient space possible.
Right. So free will emerges when you try to simplify telling nice narrative
about your environment.
I think that's very possible. Yeah.
You think free will is an illusion.
So you're kind of implying that it's a useful hack.
Well, I'll say two things.
The first thing is I think I think it's very plausible to say that any organism
that's self, or any agent that's self-whether it's biological or not, any agent that self-constructs
under energy constraints is going to believe in free will. We'll get to whether it has
free will momentarily, but I think what it definitely drives is a view of yourself and
the outside world as an agential view. I think that's inescapable. So that's true for even primitive
organisms. I think so. I think that's now they don't have now obviously you have to scale down,
right? So so so they don't have for the kinds of complex medicognition that we have so they can
do long-term planning and thinking about free will and so and so on. But but the sense of agency is
really useful to accomplish a task simple or complicated.
That's right.
In all kinds of spaces, not just in obvious three-dimensional space.
I mean, we're very good that the thing is humans
are very good at detecting agency of like medium-sized objects
moving at medium speeds in the three-dimensional world.
We see a bowling ball and we see a mouse
and we immediately know what the difference is.
How we're going to move.
Mostly things you can eat or get eaten by.
Yeah. Yeah. That's our, that's our training set, right? From the time you're little,
your training set is visual data on, on this, this like little chunk of your experience.
But imagine if, imagine if, from the time that we were born, we had innate senses of your
blood chemistry. If you could feel your blood chemistry the way you can see, right? You had a high
bandwidth connection and you could feel your blood chemistry and you could see, you could feel your blood chemistry the way you can see, right? You had a high bandwidth connection and you could feel your blood chemistry and you could see,
you could sense all the things that your organs were doing.
So your pancreas, your liver, all the things.
If we had that, we would be very good at detecting intelligence in physiological space.
We would know the level of intelligence that our various organs were deploying to deal with things
that were coming to anticipate the stimuli to, you know, but we're just terrible at that.
We don't, in fact, in fact, people the stimuli to, you know, but we're just terrible at that. We don't infect, in fact, people don't even,
you know, you talk about intelligence
to these other papers, spaces,
and a lot of people think that's just crazy
because all we know is motion.
We do have access to that information.
So it's actually possible that,
so evolution could have been wanted
to construct an organism that's able to perceive
the flow of blood through your body.
The way you see an old friend and say, yo, what's up? How's the wife and the kids?
In that same way, you would see that you would feel like a connection to the liver.
Yeah. Yeah. I think, you know, maybe other people's liver,
no, just your own, because you don't have access to other people's liver.
Not yet, but you could imagine some really interesting connection, right? Like sexual selection. Like, oh, that girl's got a nice
liver. Well, that's cool. The way her blood flows, the dynamics of the blood is very interesting.
It's novel. I've never seen one of those. But you know, that's exactly what we're trying to
have fast when we judge judgment of beauty by facial symmetry and so on.
That's a half-ass assessment of exactly that,
of exactly that, because if your cells could not cooperate
enough to keep your organism symmetrical,
you can make some inferences about what else is wrong,
that's a very basic.
Interesting, yeah, so in some deep sense, actually,
that is what we're doing. We're trying to infer
how the health, we use the word healthy, but basically how functional is this biological
system looking at so I can hook up with that one and make offspring.
Yeah, well, what kind of hardware might their genomics give me
that might be useful in the future?
I wonder why evolution didn't give us a higher resolution
signal.
Like, why the whole peacock thing with the feathers,
it doesn't seem the very low bandwidth signal
for sexual selection.
I'm going to, and I'm not an expert on this stuff,
but peacocks.
Well, you know, but I'll take a stab at the reason.
I think that it's because it's an arms race.
You see, you don't want everybody to know everything about you.
So I think that as much as much as, and in fact,
there's another interesting part of this arms race,
which is, if you think about this, the most adaptive,
evolvedable system is one that has the most level of top down control.
If it's really easy to say to a bunch of cells,
make another finger versus, okay,
here's 10,000 gene expression changes that you need to do to make it to change your finger.
The system with good top down control that has memory and then we need to get back to that.
By the way, that's a question I've been neglect the answer about where the memory is and so on.
A system that uses all of that is really highly available and that's fantastic.
But guess what? It's also highly subject to hijacking by parasites, by
by by cheaters of various kinds, by conspecifics.
Like we found that and then that goes back to the story of the pattern memory in this
in this plenary.
There's a bacterium that lives on these plenary.
That bacterium has an input into how many heads
the worm is gonna have, because it's hijacks
that control system, and it's able to make a chemical
that basically interfaces with the system
that calculates how many heads you're supposed to have,
and they can have to, and they can make them have two heads.
And so you can imagine that if you are two,
so you wanna be understandable for your own parts
to understand each other,
but you don't wanna be too understandable
because you'll be too easily controllable.
And so I think that my guess is that that opposing pressure
keeps this from being a super high band with kind of thing
where we can just look at somebody
and know everything about them.
So it's a kind of biological game of Texas Holdham.
Yeah, you showing some cards and you're hiding other cards and it's part of it and there's bluffing and there's
and all that and then there's probably whole species that would do weight and which bluffing.
That's probably where Peacocks fall. There's a book that I don't remember if I read or if I
wrote if I read some of these of the book but it's about the evolution of beauty and birds,
what's that from?
Is that a book or does Richard Dawkins talk about it,
but basically there's some species
start to like over-select for beauty,
not over-select, they just,
summaries and select for beauty.
There is a case to be made,
actually now I'm starting to remember.
I think Darwin himself made a case that
you can select based on beauty alone. So that beauty, there's a point where beauty doesn't
represent some underlying biological truth. You start to select for beauty itself. And I think
the deep question is there is some evolutionary value to beauty.
But it's an interesting kind of thought that this
can we deviate completely from the deep biological truth to actually appreciate some kind of
the summarization in itself. Let me get back to memory because this is a really interesting idea.
itself. Let me give back to memory because this is a really interesting idea. How do a collection of cells
remember anything? How do biological systems remember anything? How is that akin to the kind of memory we think of humans as having within our big cognitive engine? Yeah. One of the ways to start
thinking about bioelectricity is to ask ourselves where did neurons and all these cool tricks
that the brain uses to run these amazing problem-solving
abilities on and basically an electrical network.
Where did that come from?
They did just up here out of nowhere.
It must have evolved from something.
And what it evolved from was a much more ancient ability
of cells to form networks to solve other kinds
of problems, for example, to navigate morph of space, to control the body's shape.
And so all of the components of neurons, so eye on channels, neurotransmitter machinery,
electrical synapses, all this stuff is way older than brains, way older than neurons, in
fact older than multicellularity.
And so it was already, even bacterial biofilms, there's some beautiful work from UCSD on, on, on, on brain-like dynamics
and bacterial biofilms. So evolution figured out very early on that electrical networks are
amazing at having memories, that integrating information across distance, at different kinds
of optimization tasks, you know, image recognition and so on, long before there were brains.
tasks, you know, image recognition and so on, long before there were brains.
He actually stood back, we'll return to it.
What is bioelectricity?
What is biochemistry? What is, what are electrical networks?
I think a lot of the biology community focuses on the chemicals
as them signaling mechanisms that make the whole thing work.
You have, I think, to a large
degree uniquely, maybe you can correct me on that, have focused on the bioelectricity,
which is using electricity for signaling. There's also probably mechanical knocking on
the door. So what's the difference in what's an electrical network?
Yeah, so I want to make sure and kind of give credit where credit is to so so as far back as 1903
and probably late 1800s already, people were thinking about the importance of electrical phenomena
in life. So I'm for sure not the first person to stress the importance of electricity.
So I'm for sure not the first person to stress the importance of electricity. People, there were waves of research in the 30s, in the 40s, and then again in the kind
of 70s, 80s and 90s of sort of the pioneers of bioelectricity who did some amazing work
on all this.
I think what we've done that's new is to step away from this idea that, and I'll describe
what the bioelectricity is, is to step away from the idea that, and I'll describe what the bioelectricity is, step away from the idea that, well, here's another piece of physics that you need to keep track of to understand
physiology and development, and to really start looking at this, saying,
you know, this is a privileged computational layer that gives you access to the actual cognition of the tissue of
basal cognition. So merging that developmental bio physics with ideas and cognition of computation and so on.
I think that's what we've done. That's new, but people have been talking about bi electricity
for a really long time.
And so I'll define that.
So what happens is that if you have a single cell, cell has a membrane in that membrane
are proteins called ion channels.
And those proteins allow charged molecules potassium sodium chloride to go in and out under certain circumstances.
And when there's an imbalance of those ions,
there becomes a voltage gradient across that membrane.
And so all cells, all living cells,
try to hold a particular kind of voltage difference
across that membrane, and they spend a lot of energy to do so.
When you, now, now, so that's a single cell.
When you have multiple cells, the cells sitting next
to each other, they can communicate their voltage state
to each other via a number of different ways,
but one of them is the single, the gap junction,
which is basically like a little submarine hatch,
there's just kind of docks, right?
And the ions from one side can float
at the other side and vice versa.
So...
Isn't that incredible that this of all,
is not wild?
Because that didn't exist.
Correct.
This had to be evolved and be invented.
That's right.
Somebody invented electricity in the ocean.
One of this to get invented.
Yeah.
So, I mean, it is incredible.
The guy who discovered Gab Junction's Werner Lowenstein,
I visited him, he was really old, He was really old. He discovered him. He's one what? He really discovered them.
Live probably four billion years ago. So you're give credit where credit is due.
He rediscovered Gab Junction. But when I visited him in Woods Hole maybe 20 years ago now,
he told me that he was writing
and unfortunately he passed away and I think this book never got written.
He was writing a book on gap junctions and consciousness.
And I think it would have been an incredible book because gap junctions are magic.
I'll explain why in a minute.
What happens is that just imagine the thing about both these ion channels and these gap
junctions is that many of them are themselves voltage sensitive.
So that's a voltage sensitive current conductance.
That's a transistor.
And as soon as you've invented one, immediately you now get access to from this platonic
space of mathematical truths, you get access to all of the cool things that transistors do.
So now when you have a network of cells,
not only do they talk to each other,
but they can send messages to each other,
and the differences of voltage can propagate.
Now, to neuroscientists, this is old hat,
because you see this in the brain,
this action potential, the electricity,
you can, they have these awesome movies where
you can take a transparent animal like a zebrafish,
you can literally look down and you can see all the
firings as the fish is making decisions about what to eat
and things like that.
It's amazing.
Well, your whole body is doing that all the time, just much slower.
So there are very few things that neurons do that other cells,
that all the cells in your body don't do.
They all do very similar things, just done a much slower time scale.
And whereas your brain is thinking about how to solve problems in three-dimensional space,
the cells in an embryo are thinking about how to solve problems
in anatomical space.
They're trying to have memories like,
hey, how many fingers are we supposed to have?
Well, how many do we have now?
What do we do to get from here to there?
That's the kind of problems they're thinking about.
And the reason that gap junctions are magic
is, imagine, right right from the earliest time.
I'm here are two cells. This cell, how can they communicate? Well, the simple version is this cell could send a chemical signal.
It floats over and it hits a receptor on this cell, right? Because it comes from outside, this cell can very easily tell that that came from outside. It's this whatever information is coming. That's not my information.
That information is coming from the outside.
So I can trust it.
I can ignore it.
I can do various things with it, whatever.
But I know it comes from the outside.
Now imagine instead that you have two cells with a gap junction
between them, something happens.
Let's say the cell gets poked.
There's a calcium spike, a calcium spike,
or whatever small molecule signal propagates
through the gap junction to this cell.
There's no ownership metadata on that signal. This cell does not know now that it's
didn't that it came from outside because it looks exactly like its own memories
would have looked like of being of being of whatever had happened right. So
gap junctions to some extent wipe ownership information on data which means
that if I can't if if you and I are sharing memories and we can't quite tell
who the memories belong to,
that's the beginning of a mind melt,
that's the beginning of a scale-up of cognition
from, here's me and here's you to, no, now there's just us.
So the enforce a collective intelligence.
That's our gap junctions.
That's right.
It helps it's the beginning.
It's not the whole story, but any means, but it's the start.
Where's state stored of the system?
So is it in part in the gap junction themselves?
Is it in the cells?
There are many, many layers to this as always in biology.
So there are chemical networks.
So for example, gene regulatory networks, right?
Which are basically any kind of chemical pathway
where different chemicals activate and repress each other,
they can store memories.
So in the dynamical system sense, they can store memories.
They can get into stable states that are hard to pull them out of, right?
So that becomes once they get in, that's a memory, a permanent memory of some or a semi-permanent
memory of something that's happened.
There are cytoskeletal structures that are physically, they store memories in physical
configuration.
There are electrical memories like flip-flops where there is no
physical, right? So if you look, I show my students this example as a flip-flop and the reason
that it stores is Euro-01 is not because some piece of the hardware moved. It's because
there's a cycling of the current in one side of the thing. If I come over and I hold the other side to a high voltage for a brief period of time,
it flips over and now it's here.
But none of the hardware moved.
The information is in a stable dynamical sense.
If you were to x-ray the thing, you couldn't tell me if it was zero or one.
All you would see is where the hardware is.
You wouldn't see the energetic state of the system.
There are biological states
that are held in that exact way,
like volatile RAM basically,
like in the electrical status.
It's very akin to the different ways
the memory stored in a computer.
So there's RAM, there's hard drives.
You can make that mapping, right?
So I think the interesting thing is that,
based on the biology, we can have a more
sophisticated, I think we can revise some of our computer engineering methods because there
are some interesting things that biology doesn't we haven't done yet. But that mapping is
not bad. I mean, I think it works in many places.
Yeah, I wonder, because I mean, the way we build computers at the root of computer science is the idea of proof of correctness.
We program things to be perfect, reliable.
You know, this idea of resilience and robustness to unknown conditions is not as important.
So that's what biology is really good at.
So I don't know what kind of systems, I don't know how we go from a computer to a biological system in the future.
Yeah, I think that, you know, the thing about biology is all about making really important
decisions really quickly on very limited information. I mean, that's a biology is all about you have
to act, you have to act now, the stakes are very high, and you don't know most of what you need to
know to be perfect. And so there's not even an attempt to be perfect or to get a right in any sense.
There are just things like active inference,
minimize surprise, optimize some efficiency and some things like this.
That guides the whole business.
I mentioned to offline that some of you use a fan of your work as Andre Kapati and he's amongst many things
also writes occasionally a great blog.
He came up with this idea, I don't know if he coined the term, but of software 2.0,
where the programming is done in the space of configuring these artificial neural networks.
Is there some sense in which that would be the future of programming for us humans, where
we're less doing like Python like programming and more, how would you, how would that look
like, but basically doing the hyper parameters of
Something akin to a biological system and watching it go and keeping adjusting it and creating some kind of feedback loop within the system
So correct itself. Yeah, and then we watch it over time
Accomplished the goals we wanted to accomplish is that kind kind of the dream of the dogs that you describe
in your nature paper? Yeah, I mean, what you just painted is a very good description of our efforts
at regenerative medicine as a kind of somatic psychiatry. So the idea is that you're not trying to
micro-manage. I mean, think about the limitations of a lot of the medicines today.
We try to interact down at the level of pathways,
so we're trying to micromanage it.
What's the problem?
Well, one problem is that for almost every medicine,
other than antibiotics, once you stop it,
the problem comes right back.
You haven't fixed anything.
You were addressing symptoms. You weren't actually can do things that way, but my God, it's hard to program it.
You write at the hardware level. So, you know, I'm going to, I'm going to, I'm going to try to program this computer
by changing the melting point of copper. Like, maybe you can do things that way, but my God, it's hard to, to program it.
So, I'm going to, I'm going to try to, I'm going to try to program this computer by changing the melting point of copper. Like, maybe you can do things that way, but my God, it's hard to program at the hardware level.
So what I think we're starting to understand is that,
and by the way, this goes back to what you were saying before,
about that we could have access to our internal state.
So people who practice that kind of stuff, right?
So yoga and biofeedback and those.
Those are all the people that uniformly will say things like,
well, the body has an intelligence and this and that.
Like those two sets overlap perfectly
because that's exactly right.
Because once you start thinking about it that way,
you realize that the better locus of control
is not always at the lowest level.
This is why we don't all program with a soldering iron, right?
We take advantage of the high level intelligences that are there, which means trying to figure out, okay, which of your
tissues can learn, what can they learn, why is it that certain drugs stop working
after you take them for a while with this impetuation, right? And so can we
understand habituation, sensitization, associative learning, these kinds of
things in chemical pathways, we're going to have a completely different way, I think.
We're going to have a completely different way of using drugs and of medicine in general
when we start focusing on the goal states and on the intelligence of our subsystems as
opposed to treating everything as if the only path was micro management from chemistry
upwards.
Can you speak to this idea of somatic psychiatry? What are somatic cells?
How do they form networks that use bioelectricity to have memory and all those kinds of things?
What are somatic cells, like basics here?
Somatic cells just means the cells of your body.
So what just means body, right?
So somatic cells are just the, I'm not even specifically making a distinction between somatic
cells and stem cells or anything like that.
I mean, basically all the cells in your body, not just neurons, but all the cells in your body.
The form electrical networks during embryogenesis, during regeneration, what those networks are doing
in part is processing information about what our current shape is and what the goal shape is. Now,
how do I know this? Because I can give you a couple of examples. One example is when we started studying this, we said, okay, here's a plenary.
A plenary is a flatworm.
It has one head and one tail normally.
And the amazing, several amazing things about plenary, but basically, they kind of, I
think plenary holds the answer to pretty much every deep question of life.
For one thing, they're similar to our ancestor.
So they have true symmetry, they have a true brain, they're not like earthworms, they're much more advanced life form.
They have lots of different internal organs, but they're these little, they're about, you know,
maybe two centimeters in the centimeter to two in size. They have a head and a tail.
And the first thing is plenary are immortal. So they do not age. There's no such thing as an
old plenary. So for that right there tells you that these theories of thermodynamic limitations of on lifespan
are wrong.
It's not that well over time of everything to great.
No, planaria can keep it going for probably, you know, how long if they've been around
400 million years, right?
So these are the actually, so the planaria in our lab are actually in physical continuity
with planaria that we're here 400 million years ago.
So there's planaria that have lived that long, essentially.
What does it mean physical continuity?
Because what they do is they split in half.
The way they reproduce is they split in half.
So the Plenary, the back end grabs the Petri dish,
the front end takes off and they rip themselves in half.
But isn't it some sense that we're like,
you are a physical continuation? Yes, except that except that we go through a bottleneck
of one cell, which is the egg, they do not. I mean, they can. There's certain plenary of that.
God, so we go through a very ruthless compression process. Yes, yes, they don't. Yes, like an auto
encoder, you know, you sort of squash down to one cell and then back out. These, these guys just
tear themselves in half and then each and then and so the other amazing thing about them is they
regenerate. So you can cut them into pieces. the record is I think 276 or something like that by Thomas
Hans Morgan.
Uh, and each piece regrow a perfect little worm.
They know exactly every piece knows exactly what's missing what needs to happen.
Uh, in fact, in fact, if you chop it in half as it grows the other half.
Uh, the original, the original tissue shrinks
so that when the new tiny head shows up,
they're proportional.
So it keeps, it keeps perfect proportion.
If you starve them, they shrink, if you feed them,
again, they expand, they're controlled,
their anatomical control is just insane.
Somebody cut them into over 200 pieces.
Yeah, yeah, Thomas Hunt Morgan did.
Hashtag science.
Yeah, amazing.
And maybe more, I mean, they didn't have antibiotics back then.
I bet he lost some due to infection.
I bet it's actually more than that.
I bet you could do more than that.
Humans can do that.
Well, yes, I mean, again, true.
Except that you can't at the embryonic level.
Well, that's the thing, right?
So I tell, when I talk about this, I
said just remember that as amazing as it is to grow a whole
planarian from a tiny fragment, half of the human population can grow a full body from one cell, right?
So development is really, you can look at development as a, as just an example of regeneration.
Yeah, to think, we'll talk about regenerative medicine, but there's some sense what would
be like that warm in like 500 years where I think we should go re-grow hand.
Yep. With given time, it takes time to grow large things.
For now.
Yeah, I think so.
I think it probably, it's why not accelerate.
Oh, biology takes its time.
I'm not going to say anything is impossible, but I don't know of a way to accelerate these
processes.
I think it's possible.
I think we are going to be regenerative, but I don't know if a way to make it fast.
I've just think people from a few centuries from now, I'd be like, well, they have to,
they used to have to wait a week for the hand to grow. It's like when the microwave was invented,
you can, you can toast here. What's that called when you put a cheese on a toast?
It's delicious, it's all I know. I'm blanking, and you.
All right, so Plenary, why were we talking about
the magical Plenary that they have the mystery of life?
Yeah, so the reason we're talking about Plenary
is not only are they immortal, okay?
Not only do they regenerate every part of the body,
they generally don't get cancer, right?
So which we can talk about why that's important.
They're smart.
They can learn things.
So you can train them.
And it turns out that if you train a plenary and then cut their heads off, the tail will
regenerate a brand new brain that still remembers the original information.
Do they have a biological network going on?
Yes.
Yes.
So their somatic cells are forming a network.
And that's what you mean by true brain.
What's the requirement for a true brain?
Like everything else, it's a continuum,
but a true brain has certain characteristics
as far as the density, like a localized density
of neurons that guides behavior.
In the head.
Exactly, exactly.
If you cut their head off, the tail doesn't have,
that doesn't do anything, it just sits there
until the new brain is, you know,
until a new brain regenerates. They have all the same neurotransmitters that you
and I have. But here's why, here's what we're talking about them in this, in this context.
So here's your planary, you cut off the head, you cut off the tail, you have a middle fragment.
That middle fragment has to make one head and one tail. How does it know how many of each to make
and where do they go? How come it doesn't switch? How come, right? So, so we did a very simple thing and we
said, okay, let's, let's make the hypothesis that there's a somatic electrical network
that remembers the correct pattern and that what it's doing is, is recalling that memory
and building to that pattern. So we did was, we used a, a way to visualize electrical
activity in these cells, right? It's a, it's a, it's a variant of what people use to look
for electricity in the brain. And we saw that it has a, that? It's a variant of what people use to look for electricity in the brain.
And we saw that it has a, that that fragment has a very, very particular electrical pattern.
You can literally see it once, once we developed the technique. It has a very particular electrical
pattern that shows you where the head and the tail goes, right? You can, you can just see it.
And then we said, okay, well, now let's test the idea that that's a memory that actually controls
where the head and the tail goes.
Let's change that pattern.
So basically, incept the false memory.
And so what you can do is you can do that in many different ways, one ways with drugs
that target ion channels to say, and so you pick these drugs and you say, okay, I'm going
to do it so that instead of this one head one tail, pat electrical pattern, you have a
two headed pattern, right?
You're just editing the electrical information in the network. When you do that, I guess, what the cells build. They build a two-headed worm.
And the coolest thing about it, now, no genetic changes. So we haven't touched the genome. The genome
is totally wild type. But the amazing thing about it is that when you take these two-headed animals
and you cut them into pieces again, some of those pieces will continue to make two-headed animals.
So that information, that memory, that electrical circuit,
not only does it hold the information for how many heads,
not only does it use that information to tell the cells
what to do to regenerate, but it stores it.
Once you've recetted it keeps.
And we can go back, we can take a two-headed animal
and put it back to one-headed.
So now imagine, so there's a couple of interesting things here
that have implications for understanding
what abagenomes and things like that.
Imagine I take this two-headed animal.
I went by the way, when they reproduce,
when they tear themselves in half,
you still get two-headed animals.
So imagine I take them, and I throw them in the Charles River
over here.
So 100 years later, some scientists come along,
and they scoop up some samples, and they go,
oh, there's a single-headed form, and a two-headed form.
Wow, a speciation event.
Cool.
Let's sequence the genome and see why, what happened?
The genome's identical.
It's nothing wrong with the genome. So if you ask the question, how does,. Let's sequence the genome and see why, what happened? The genome is identical.
It's nothing wrong with the genome.
So, if you ask the question, how does, so this goes back to your very first question,
is where do body plans come from, right?
How does the plenary know how many heads it's supposed to have?
Now, it's interesting, because you could say DNA, but what happened, what, what, as it
turns out, the DNA produces a piece of hardware that by default says one hit, the way that when you turn on a calculator by default,
it's a zero every single time, right? When you turn it on, it says zero. But it's a programmable calculator as it turns out.
So once you've changed that, next time, it won't say zero, it'll say something else in the same thing here.
So you can make one hit, two hit, and you can make no-headed worms. We've done some other things along these lines, some other really weird constructs.
We've done some other things along these lines, some other really weird constructs. So, so this this this question of right is so again, it's really important.
The hardware software distinction is really important because the hardware is essential
because without proper hardware you're never going to get to the right physiology of having
that memory.
But once you have it, it doesn't fully determine what the information is going to be.
You can have other information in there and it's reprogrammable by us, by bacteria, by various parasites, probably, things like that.
The other amazing thing about these planaries, think about this. Most animals, when we get a
mutation in our bodies, our children don't inherit it, right? So you can go on, you can run around
for 50, 60 years getting mutations, your children don't have those mutations, because we go through
the egg stage. Plenary tear themselves in half, and that's how they reproduce.
So for 400 million years, they keep every mutation that they've had that doesn't kill the
cell that it's in.
So when you look at these plenary, their bodies are what's called mixed-apploid, meaning
that every cell might have a different number of chromosomes.
They look like a tumor.
If you look at the genome is incredible mess because they accumulate all this stuff.
And yet, their body structure is,
they are the best regenerators on the planet.
Their anatomy is rock solid,
even though their genome is all kinds of crap.
So this is kind of a scandal, right?
That when we learn, what are genomes to what?
Genomes determine your body.
Okay, why is the animal with the worst genome
have the best anatomical control?
The most cancer resistant, the most regenerative, right?
Really we're just beginning to start to understand this relationship between the genomically
determined hardware.
And by the way, just as a couple of months ago, I think I now somewhat understand why this
is, but it's really a major puzzle.
I mean, that really throws a wrench into the whole nature versus nurture, because you usually associate electricity with
the nurture and the hardware with the nature.
And there's just this weird integrated mess that propagates to generations.
Yeah, it's much more fluid, it's much more complex.
You can imagine what's happening here.
It's just imagine the evolution of an animal like this.
That multi-scale, this goes back to this multi-scale
competence here.
Imagine that you have an animal that, where it's,
its tissues have some degree of multi-scale competency.
So for example, if we saw in the tag pool,
if you put an eye on its tail, they can still
see out of that eye, right?
That the you know, there's all this incredible plasticity. So if you have an animal and it comes up for selection and the fitness is quite good.
Evolution doesn't know whether the fitness is good because the genome was awesome or because the genome was kind of junky
But but the competency made up for it, right? And things kind of ended up good.
So what that means is that the more competency you have,
the harder it is for selection to pick the best genomes.
It hides information, right?
And so that means that, so what happens,
you know, evolution basically starts,
although it starts, all the hard work
is being done to increase the competency
because it's harder and harder to see the genomes.
And so I think in Plenary of what happened
is that there's this runaway phenomenon
where all the effort went into the algorithm such that we know you got a crappy genome.
We can't keep, we can't clean up the genome.
We can't keep track of it.
So what's going to happen is what survives are the algorithms that can create a great worm
no matter what the genome is.
So everything went into the algorithm,
and which of course then reduces the pressure on keeping a clean genome.
So this idea of, and different animals have this in different levels,
but this idea of putting energy into an algorithm that
does not over train on priors.
It can't assume, I mean, I think biologies this way in general,
evolution doesn't take the past too seriously because it makes these
basically problem solving machines as opposed to like exactly what you know to deal with exactly what happened last time
Yeah problem solving versus memory recall
So little memory but a lot of problem solving. I think so yeah in many cases. Yeah problem solving
I mean it's incredible that those kinds of systems are able to be constructed, especially
how much they contrast with where we build problem solving systems in the AI world.
Back to Xenobots.
I'm not sure if we ever described how Xenobots are built, but you have a paper titled Biological
Robots, Perspectives on an Emerging Interdisciplinary Field, and in me add, you have a paper titled Biological Robots, Perspectives on an Emerging
Interdisciplinary Field, and in the beginning, you mentioned that the word xenobots is like
controversial. Do you guys get in trouble for using xenobots or what, do people not like the
word xenobots? Are you trying to be provocative with the word xenobots versus biological robots?
I don't know. Is there some drama that we should
be aware of? There's a little bit of drama. I think the drama is basically related to people
having very fixed ideas about what terms mean. I think in many cases, these ideas are completely
out of date with where science is now. For sure, they're out of date with what's going to be,
these concepts are not going to survive
the next couple of decades.
So if you ask a person, and including a lot of people
in biology who kind of want to keep a sharp distinction
between biologicals and robots, right?
See, what's a robot?
Well, a robot, it comes out of a factory.
It's made by humans.
It is boring. It is meaning that you can predict everything it's going to do. It's made of metal and
certain other inorganic materials, living organisms are magical. They arise, right? Then so on. So
these these distinctions, I think these these distinctions, I think, were never good, but they're going
to be completely useless going forward. And so part of this, a couple of papers that,
that's one paper, this another one,
that Josh Bongarde and I wrote,
where we really attack the terminology.
And we say these binary categories
are based on very non-essential kind of surface limitations
of technology and imagination that were true before,
but they've got to go.
And so we call them xenobots.
So, xenophyrzenopus lavas, where thisvis, it's the frog that these guys are made of, but we think it's
an example of a biobot technology because ultimately, once we understand how to communicate
and manipulate the inputs to these cells, we will be able to get them to build whatever we want them to build.
And that's robotics, right? It's the rational construction of machines that have useful purposes.
I absolutely think that this is a robotics platform, whereas some biologists don't.
But it's built in a way that all the different components are doing their own computation.
So in a way that we've been talking about, you're trying to do top-down control in that biological system. And in the future,
all of this will merge together because of course at some point we're going to throw in synthetic
biology circuits, new transcriptional circuits to get them to do new things. Of course, we'll
throw some of that in, but we specifically stayed away from all of that because in the first few papers,
and there's some more coming down the pike that are I think going to be pretty pretty dynamite
That we want to show what the native cells are made of because what happens is you know if you engineer the heck out of them
Right if we were to put in new you know new transcription factors and some new metabolic machinery and whatever
People will say okay you engineered this and you made it do whatever and fine
I wanted to show, and the whole team
wanted to show the plasticity and the intelligence
and the biology.
What does it do that's surprising
before you even start manipulating the hardware
in that way?
Yeah, don't try to over-control the thing.
Let it flourish.
The full beauty of the biology,
because it's the wise Zenipus Levis. Levis, how do you pronounce it? The frog. Zen of the Bellagic system. Why is Xenopus levis?
Lavis, how do you pronounce it? The frog? Xenopus levis. Yeah, it's a very popular.
Why this frog? It's been used since I think the 50s. It's just very convenient because
you can, you know, we keep the adults in this very fine frog habitat. They lay eggs. They lay
tens of thousands of eggs at a time. The eggs develop right in front of your eyes.
It's the most magical thing you can see
because normally, if you were to deal with mice or rabbits
or whatever, you don't see the early stages
or everything's inside them other.
Here, everything's in a petri dish at room temperature.
So you have an egg, it's fertilized,
and you can just watch it divide and divide and divide
and all the organs form.
You can just see it.
And at that point, the community has developed lots
of different tools for understanding what's going on
and also for manipulating, right?
So it's people use it for understanding birth defects
and neurobiology and cancer immunology also.
So you get the whole embryogenesis in the peatured dish.
That's so cool to watch.
Is there videos of this?
Oh yeah, yeah, yeah.
There's amazing videos online.
I mean, mammalian embryos are super cool too.
For example, monosigotic twins are what happens
when you cut a mammalian embryo in half.
You don't get two half bodies.
You get two perfectly normal bodies
because it's a regeneration event.
Development is just the kind of regeneration, really.
And why this particular frog?
It's just because they were doing in the 50s and it
breeds well in, you know, in, in, it's easy to raise in the laboratory and it's very prolific
and all the tools basically for decades, people have been developing tools. There's other,
some people use other frogs, but I have to say this is, this is, this is important. Zennabots
are fundamentally not anything about frogs. So I can't say too much about this because it's not published in peer review yet,
but we've made Zenobots out of other things that have nothing to do with frogs.
This is not a frog phenomenon. We started with frog because it's so convenient,
but this plasticity is not a frog. It's not related to the fact that they're frogs.
What happens when you kiss it does it turn to a prince?
No, or a princess, which way?
Prince, yeah, prince.
It should be a prince.
Yeah, that's an experiment that I don't believe we've done.
And if we have, I don't know what we're going to do.
We're going to collaborate.
I can take on the lead on that effort.
OK, cool.
How does the source coordinate?
Let's focus in on just the embryogenesis.
So there's one cell.
So it divides, doesn't have to be very
careful about what it's cell starts doing once they divide. And like, when there's three of them,
it's like the co-founders or whatever, like, like, slow down, you're responsible for this. When do
they become specialized and how do they coordinate that specialization?
So, this is the basic science of developmental biology.
There's a lot known about all of that, but I'll tell you what I think is the most important part,
which is, yes, it's very important who does what?
However, because going back to this issue of, I made this claim that biology doesn't take
the past too seriously.
And what I mean by that is it doesn't assume that everything is the way it's expected
to be, right?
And here's an example of that.
This was done.
This was an old experiment going back to the 40s.
But basically imagine, it's a new salamander.
And it's got these little twobules that go to the kidneys.
This little tube, take a cross-section of that tube,
you see 8 to 10 cells that have cooperated to make this little tube in cross-section.
So one amazing thing you can do is you can mess with a very early cell division
to make the cells gigantic.
You can make them different sizes.
You can force them to be different sizes.
So if you make the cells different sizes, the whole new is still the same size. So if you take a cross section
through that tubule, instead of 8 to 10 cells, you might have 4 or 5, or you might have 3, until
you make the cells so enormous that one single cell wraps around itself and gives you that same large scale structure
where it completely different molecular mechanism.
So now instead of cell to cell communication to make a tubule,
instead of that, it's one cell using the cytoskeleton
to bend itself around.
So think about what that means.
And the service of a large scale,
it talk about top down control, right?
And the service of a large scale and atomical feature,
different molecular mechanisms get called up.
So now, think about this.
You're a new selling, trying to make an embryo.
If you had a fixed idea of who was supposed to do what,
it'd be screwed because now your cells are gigantic.
Nothing would work.
The, there's an incredible tolerance for changes
in the size of the parts, in the amount of DNA
in those parts, all sorts of stuff.
You can, the life is highly interoperable.
You can put electrodes in there.
You can put weird nanomaterials.
It still works.
This is that problem-solving action.
It's able to do what it needs to do even when circumstances change.
The hallmark of intelligence, William James defined intelligence as the ability to get
to the same goal by different means. That's this. You get to the same goal by completely different
means. And so, so, so why am I bringing this up? It's just to say that, yeah, it's important
for the cells to do the right stuff, but they have incredible tolerances for things not
being what you expect and to still get their job done. So, if you're, you know, all of
these things are not hardwired. There are organisms that might be hardwired.
For example, the nematode C elegans,
in that organism, every cell is numbered,
meaning that every C elegans has exactly
the same number of cells as every other C elegans.
They're all in the same place.
They all divide.
There's literally a map of how it works.
That in that sort of system, it's much more cookie cutter.
But most organisms are incredibly plastic in that way.
Is there something particularly magical to you about the whole developmental biology process?
Is there something you could say? Because you just said it. They're very good at accomplishing the
goal of the job they need to do, the competency thing, but you get freaking organisms from one cell.
but it's the thing, but you get a freaking organism from one cell.
It's like, uh, I mean, it's very hard, hard to intuit that whole process.
Do you even think about reverse engineering that process?
Right. Very hard to the point where I often, it just imagine I, I, I sometimes ask my students to do this thought experiment. Imagine you were, you were shrunk down to
the, to the scale of a single cell and you were in the middle of an embryo and you were looking around at what's
going on. And the cells running around, some cells are dying at the, you know, every time
you look, it's kind of a different number of cells for most organisms. And so I think
that if you didn't know what embryonic development was, you would have no clue that what you're
seeing is always going to make the same thing. Never mind knowing what that is. Never mind
being able to say, even with full genomic information being able to say, what the hell are they building? We
have no way to do that. But just even to guess that, wow, the outcome of all this activity is,
it's always going to be, it's always going to build the same thing.
The imperative to create the final U as you are now is there already. So you can, you would, so she started from the same
embryo, you create a very similar organism.
Yeah, on except for cases like the xenobuts, when you give them a different environment, they
come up with a different way to be adaptive in that environment. But overall, I mean,
so I think, so I think to, you know, kind of summarize it, I think what evolution is really good at is creating
hardware that has a very stable baseline mode, meaning that it's left to its own devices.
It's very good at doing the same thing, but it has a bunch of problem solving capacity
such that if any assumptions don't hold, if your cells are a weird size or you get the
wrong number of cells or there's somebody, you know, somebody stuck an electrode halfway through the body,
whatever, it will still get most of what it needs to do done.
You've talked about the magic and the power of biology here. If you look at the human brain,
how special is the brain in this context? You're kind of minimizing the importance of
the brain. Or, lessening it's, we think of all the special
computation happens in the brain.
Everything else is like the help.
You're kind of saying that the whole thing is,
the whole thing is doing computation.
But nevertheless, how special is the human brain
in this full context of biology?
Yeah, I mean, look, there's no getting away from the fact
that the human brain allows us to do things
that we could not do without it.
You can say the same thing about the liver.
Yeah, no, this is true.
And so, you know, my goal is not, you're right,
my goal is not.
You're just being polite to the brain right now.
Well, you're being a politician.
Like, listen, everybody has a role.
Yeah, it's a very important role.
That's right.
We have to acknowledge the importance of the brain, you know.
There are more than enough people who are cheerleading
the brain, right?
So I don't feel like nothing I say is going to reduce people's
excitement about the human brain.
And so I emphasize other things.
I don't think it gets too much credit.
I think other things don't get enough credit.
I think the brain is, the human brain is incredible
and special and all that.
I think other things need more credit.
And I also think that this, and I'm sort of this way
about everything.
I don't like binary categories, but almost anything.
I like a continuum.
And the thing about the human brain is that it,
by accepting that as some kind of an important category
or essential thing,
we end up with all kinds of weird pseudo problems and conundrum.
So for example, when we talk about it,
if you want to talk about ethics and other things like that.
And what, you know, this idea that surely, if we look out into the universe, surely, we
don't believe that this human brain is the only way to be sentient, right?
Surely, we don't, you know, and to have high level cognition.
I just can't even wrap my mind around this idea that that is the only way to do it.
No doubt there are other architectures made of completely different principles that achieve the same thing. And once we believe
that, then that tells us something important. It tells us that things that are not quite
human brains or chimeras of human brains and other tissue or human brains or other kinds
of brains and novel configurations or things that are sort of brains, but not really or plants or embryos or whatever might also have important cognitive status.
So that's the only thing.
I think we have to be really careful about treating the human brain as if it was some kind
of like sharp binary category, you know, you are or you aren't.
I don't believe that exists.
So when we look at all the beautiful variety of semi-biological architectures out there
in the universe, how many intelligent alien civilizations do you think are out there?
Boy, I have no expertise in that whatsoever. You haven't met any. I have met the ones we've made. I think that I mean exactly in some sense
with synthetic biology are you not creating aliens? I absolutely think so because because look all of life
all of all standard model systems are an end of one course of evolution on earth right and trying to
make conclusions about biology from looking at life on Earth is like testing your theory on the same data that generated.
It's all kind of like locked in. So we absolutely have to create novel examples that have no history of selection to be a good zen about the cells have selection for various things,
but the zen about itself never existed before.
And so we can make chimeras, we make frog allotals
that are sort of half frog, have axol.
You can make all sorts of high brats,
constructions of living tissue with robots
and whatever.
We need to be making these things
until we find actual aliens, because otherwise,
we're just looking at an end of one set of examples,
all kinds of frozen accidents of evolution and so on.
We need to go beyond that to really understand biology.
But we're still even when you do a synthetic biology,
you're locked in to the basic components of the way biology is done on this earth.
Yeah, yeah, still limited.
And also the basic constraints of the environment even artificial
environments that construct in the lab are tied up to the environment.
I mean, what do you?
Okay, let's say there is I mean what I think is there is a
nearly infinite number of intelligence civilizations living or dead out there.
If you pick one out of the box, what do you think it would look like? number of intelligence civilizations living or dead out there.
If you pick one out of the box, what would you think it would look like?
So in when you think about synthetic biology or creating synthetic organisms,
how hard is it to create something that's very different?
Yeah, I think it's very hard to create something that's very different, right?
It's, we are just locked in both,
both experimentally and in terms of our imagination,
it's very hard.
And you also emphasize several times the idea of shape.
Yeah.
The individual cell get together with other cells
and they kinda, they going to build a shape.
So it's shape and function, but shape is a critical thing.
Yeah. So here I'll take a stab.
I mean, I agree with you to whatever extent that we can say anything.
I do think that there's probably an infinite number of different,
different architectures with that are with interest and cognitive properties
out there. What can we say about them? I think that the only things that are going... I don't think we can
rely on any of the typical stuff, you know, carbon-based, like I think all of that is just, you know,
us having a lack of imagination. But I think the things that are going to be universal if anything is are things, for example, driven
by resource limitation, the fact that you are fighting a hostile world and you have to
draw a boundary between yourself and the world somewhere.
The fact that that boundary is not given to you by anybody, you have to estimate it yourself.
In the fact that you have to coarse-grained your experience and the fact that you're
going to try to minimize surprise and the fact that these are the things that you have to coarse grain your experience and the fact that you're gonna try to minimize surprise
and the fact that, like these are the things
that I think are fundamental about biology.
None of the facts about the genetic code
or even the fact that we have genes
or the biochemistry, but I don't think any of those things
are fundamental, but it's gonna be a lot more
about the information and about the creation of the self,
the fact that, so in my framework,
selves are demarcated by the scale of the goals that they can pursue.
So from little tiny local goals to massive planetary scale goals for
certain humans and everything in between.
So you can draw this cognitive light cone that determines the scale of the
goals you could possibly pursue.
I think those kinds of frameworks like that, like active inference and so on
are going to be universally applicable, but none of the other things that are typically
discussed.
Quick pause, Dean of Bathroom Break.
We were just talking about aliens and all that and that's a funny thing which is, yeah,
I don't know if you've seen them, there's a kind of debate that goes on about cognition
and plants.
What can you say about different kinds of computation and cognition and plants?
And I always look at that stuff.
If you're weirded out by cognition and plants,
you're not ready for exobiology, right?
If something that's that similar here on Earth
is already freaking you out,
then I think there's going to be all kinds of cognitive life
out there that we're going to have a really hard time
recognizing.
I think robots will help us, like expand our mind about cognition.
Either that or the word like a xenobots.
So and they maybe becomes the same thing is, you know, really,
when the human engineer is the thing, at least in part,
and then is able to achieve some kind of cognition that's different than what you're when the human engineer is the thing, at least in part,
and then is able to achieve some kind of cognition
that's different than what you're used to,
then you start to understand like,
oh, you know, every living organisms capable of cognition,
oh, I need to kind of broaden my understanding
what cognition is, but do you think plants,
like when you eat them, are they screaming?
I don't know about screaming. I think you have to.
That's what I think when I eat a salad. Yeah.
Good. Yeah.
I think you have to scale down the expectations in terms of, right?
So probably the not screaming in the way that we would be screaming.
However, there's plenty of data on plants being able to do anticipation
and certain kinds of memory and so on. I think, you know think what you just said about robots, I hope you're right and I hope that's, but there's
two ways that people can take that.
One way is exactly what you just said to try to expand their notions for that category.
The other way people often go is they just sort of define the term.
If it's not a natural product, it's just faking, right?
It's not really intelligence if it was made by somebody else
because it's that same, it's the same thing.
They can see how it's done.
And once you see how it's like a magic trick
when you see how it's done, it's not as fun anymore.
And I think people have a real tendency for that.
And they sort of, which I find really strange
in the sense that if somebody said to me, we have
this sort of blind, like a hill climbing search.
And then we have a really smart team of engineers, which one
do you think is going to produce a system that
has good intelligence?
I think it's really weird to say that it only comes from the blind
search, right?
It can't be done by people who, by the way, can also use evolutionary techniques if they
want to, but also rational design.
I think it's really weird to say that real intelligence only comes from natural evolution.
So, I hope you're right.
I hope people take it the other way.
Well, there's a nice shortcut.
So, I work with a leg of robots a lot now for my own personal pleasure, not in that way, internet,
so four legs. And one of the things that changes my experience of the robots a lot is,
when I can't understand why I did a certain thing. And there's a lot of ways to engineer that. Me, the person that created a software that runs it,
there's a lot of ways for me to build that software
in such a way that I don't exactly know why it did
a certain basic decision.
Of course, as an engineer, you can go in
and start to look at logs, you can log all kind of data
sensory data, the decisions you made, all the
outputs and networks and so on. But I also try to really experience that surprise and that
really experience as another person would totally doesn't know how it's built. And I think
the magic is there and not knowing how it works. That I think biology does that for you through the layers of abstraction.
Because nobody really knows what's going on inside the biologicals.
Like each one component is clueless about the big picture.
I think there's actually really cheap systems that can illustrate that kind of thing, which is even like, you know,
fractals, right? Like you have a very small short formula in Z and you see it. And there's
no magic, you're just going to crank through, you know, Z squared plus Z, whatever, you're
just going to crank through it. But the result of it is this incredibly rich, beautiful
image, right? That just like, wow, all of that was in this like 10 character long
string, like amazing. So the fact that you can, you can know everything there is to know
about the details and the process and all the parts and everything, like there's literally
no magic of any kind there. And yet the outcome is something that you would never have expected
and it's just, it just, you know, is incredibly rich and complex and beautiful.
So there's a lot of that.
You write the, you work on developing conceptual frameworks
for understanding unconventional cognition.
So the kind of thing we've been talking about,
I just like the term unconventional cognition.
And you want to figure out how to detect studying,
communicate with a thing.
You've already mentioned a few examples, but what is unconventional cognition?
Is it as simply as everything outside of what we define usually as cognition,
cognitive science, the stuff going on between our ears, or is there some deeper way
to get at the fundamentals of what is cognition?
Yeah, I think like, and I know I'm certainly not the only person who works in unconventional cognition.
So it's the term used.
Yeah, that's one that I so I've coined a number of weird terms, but that's not one of mine.
Like that, that's an existing thing.
So so for example, somebody like Andy Adam Ascii, who I don't know if you've, if you've had him on,
if you haven't, you, you should, he's a, he's a, he's a, he's a, you know, very interesting guy.
He's a computer scientist and he does unconventional cognition and slime molds and all kinds of
weird, he's a real weird cat, really interesting.
Anyway, so that's, you know, there's a bunch of terms that I've come up with, but that's
not one of mine.
So, I think like many terms, that one is really defined by the times, meaning that unconventional
cognition, things that are unconventional cognition today are not going
to be considered unconventional cognition at some point.
It's one of those things.
And so it's this really deep question of how do you recognize, communicate with, classify
cognition when you cannot rely on the typical
milestones, right? So, so typical, um, you know, again, if you stick with the, with the, uh,
the history of life on earth, like these, these exact model systems, you would say, ah,
here's a particular structure of the brain. And this one has fewer of those. And this
one has a bigger frontal cortex. And this one, right. So these are, these are landmarks
that, that we're, that we're used to. And it allows us to make very
kind of rapid judgments about things. But if you can't rely on that either because you're looking at
a synthetic thing or an engineered thing or an alien thing, then what do you do? Right, how do you,
and so that's what I'm really interested in. I'm interested in mind in all of its possible
implementations, not just the obvious ones that we know
from looking at brains here on Earth.
Whenever I think about something like
unconventional cognition, I think about cellular automata.
I'm just captivated by the beauty of the thing.
The fact that from simple little objects,
you can create such beautiful complexity that very quickly you forget
about the individual objects and you see the things that it creates as its own organisms
that blows my mind every time.
Like honestly, I could full-time just eat mushrooms and watch cellular tolerance.
Don't even have to do mushrooms.
Just cellular tolerance.
It feels like, I mean, from an engineering perspective,
I love when a very simple system captures something really
powerful, because then you can study that system to understand
something fundamental about complexity, about life on earth.
Anyway, how do I communicate with a thing?
If a cellular automata can do cognition, if a plant can do cognition,
if a xenobot can do cognition, how do I like whisper in its ear and
get an answer back to, how do I have a conversation?
Yeah. Well, how do I have a conversation? Yeah.
Well, how do I have a xenobot on a podcast?
It's a really interesting line of investigation
that that opens up.
I mean, we've thought about this.
So you need a few things.
You need to understand the space in which they live.
So what, not just the physical modality,
like can they see, like, can they feel vibration?
I mean, that's important, of course,
because that's how you deliver your message. But not just the ideas modality, like can they see, like, can they feel vibration? I mean, that's important, of course, because that's how you deliver your message.
But not just the ideas for a communication medium,
not just the physical medium, but what is saliency, right?
So what are these, what are important to this,
what's important to the system?
And systems of all kinds of different levels
of sophistication of what you could expect to get back.
And I think what's really important,
I call this the spectrum of persuadability,
which is this idea that when you're looking at a system,
you can't assume where on the spectrum it is,
you have to do experiments.
And so for example, if you look at a gene regulatory network,
which is a bunch of nodes that turn each other on and off
at various rates, you might look at that and you say, well, there's no magic
here.
I mean, clearly this thing is as deterministic as it gets.
It's a piece of hardware.
The only way we're going to be able to control it is by rewiring it, which is the way my molecular
biology works, right?
We can add nodes, remove nodes, or whatever.
Well, so we've done simulations and shown that biological, and now we're doing this in
the lab, the biological
networks like that have a sociative memory. So they can actually learn, they can learn from
experience, they have habituation, they have sensitization, they have a sociative memory,
which you wouldn't have known if you assume that they have to be on the left side of that
spectrum. So when you're going to communicate with something, and we've even Charles Abramson,
I've written a paper on behaviors that approach us to synthetic
organism, meaning that if you're given something, you have no idea what it is or what it can
do.
How do you figure out what its psychology is, what its level is, what does it.
And so we literally lay out a set of protocols starting with the simplest things and then
moving up to more complex things where you can make no assumptions about what this thing
can do.
Right?
Just from you, you have to start and you'll find out. So, so when you're gonna, so, so here's a simple, I mean, here's one way to communicate with
something. If you can train it, that's a way of communicating. So if you can provide, if you can
figure out what the currency of, of reward of positive and negative reinforcement is, right?
And you can get it to do something it wasn't doing before, based on experiences you've given,
and you have taught it one thing. You have communicated one thing
that such and such an action is good.
So some other action is not good.
That's like a basic atom of primitive atom of communication.
What about in some sense,
if it gets you to do something you haven't done before,
is it answering back?
Yeah, most certainly.
And then there's, I've seen cartoons,
I think maybe Gary Larson or somebody had a cartoon
of these rats and the maze and the one rat, you know, assist to the other.
He'll look at this every time, every time I walk over here, he starts scribbling and
then, you know, on this clip, he has it's awesome.
If we step outside ourselves and really measure how much, like if I actually measure how much I've changed because of my interaction
with certain cellular automata, I mean, you really have to take that into consideration
about like, well, these things are changing you too.
Yes.
I know you know how it works and so on, but you're being changed by the thing.
Yeah.
Absolutely.
I think I read, I don't know any details,
but I think I read something about how wheat
and other things have domesticated humans in terms of,
but by their properties change the way
that human behavior and societal structure.
In that sense, cats are running the world.
Cause they took over the first, first of all.
So first, they, while not giving a shit about humans, clearly with every ounce of their
being, they've somehow got just millions and millions of humans to take them home and
feed them.
And then not only the physical space that they take over, they took over the digital space,
they dominate the internet in terms of cuteness, in terms of memability.
And so they're like, they got themselves literally inside the memes, they become viral
and spread on the internet.
And they're the ones that are probably controlling humans.
It's my theory.
Another, that's a follow-up paper after the frog kissing.
Okay.
I mean, you mentioned sentience and consciousness.
You have a paper titled, Generalizing Frameworks for Sentience Beyond Natural Species. natural species. So beyond normal cognition, if we look at
sentience and consciousness, and I wonder if you draw interesting distinction between those two
elsewhere, outside of humans, and maybe outside of earth, you think aliens have sentience.
And maybe outside of Earth, you think aliens have sentience.
And if they do, how do we think about it? So when you have this framework, what is this paper,
what is the way you propose to think about sentience?
Yeah, that particular paper was a very short commentary
on another paper that was written about crabs,
it was a really good paper on them, crabs and various,
like a rubric of different types
of behaviors that could be applied to different creatures
and they're trying to apply it to crabs and so on.
I've, conscience to this, we can talk about it
if you want, but it's a whole separate kettle of fish.
I almost never talk about crabs.
In this case, yes.
I almost never talk about consciousness per se. I've said very very little
about it, but we can we can talk about it if you want. Mostly what I talk about is cognition,
because I think that that's much easier to deal with in a kind of rigorous experimental way.
I think that all of these all of these terms have, you know, sentience and so on, have different definitions.
And I fundamentally, I think that people can, as long as they specify what they mean ahead
of time, I think people can define them in various ways.
The only thing that I really kind of insist on is that the right way to think about all
this stuff is, is an engine, from an
engineering perspective, what does it help me to control, predict, and does it help me
do my next experiment? So, that's not a universal perspective. So, some people have philosophical
kind of underpinnings and those are primary and if anything runs against
that, then it must automatically be wrong.
So some people will say, I don't care what else if your theory says to me that thermostats
have little tiny goals, I'm not, I'm not, I'm not, so that's it.
I just, like, that's my philosophical, you know, preconception that, like thermostats
do not have goals and that's it.
So, um, so that's one way of doing it and some people do it that way.
I do not do it that way and I think that we can't,
I don't think we can know much of anything
from a philosophical armchair.
I think that all of these theories and ways
of doing things stand or fall based on just basically
one set of criteria, does it help you run
a rich research program?
That's it.
If I agree with you totally, but so forget philosophy,
what about the poetry of ambiguity?
What about at the limits of the things you can engineer
using terms that can be defined in multiple ways
and living within that uncertainty
in order to play with words until something lands
that you can engineer.
I mean, that's to me what consciousness sits currently.
Nobody really understands the heart problem of consciousness, the subject, what it feels
like.
Because it really feels like it feels like something to be this biological system.
This conglomerate of a bunch of cells in this hierarchy of competency feels like something and I feel like one thing.
And is that just a side effect of a complex system or is there something more that humans
have or is there something more than any biological system has some kind of magic some kind of not just
the sense of agency but a real sense with a capital letter S of agency. Yeah.
Boy, yeah, that's a deep question now. Is there a room for poetry and engineering or no?
No, there definitely is and a lot of the poetry comes in when we realize that none of the categories we deal with are sharp
as we think they are, right?
And so in the different areas of all these spectra
are where a lot of the poetry sits.
I have many new theories about things,
but I, in fact, do not have a good theory
about consciousness that I plan to try it out.
So...
And you almost don't see it as useful for your current work
to do some unconsciousness.
I think it will come.
I have some thoughts about it, but I don't feel like they're going to move the needle yet on, on that.
But then you want to grow it in engineering always.
So well, I mean, I don't, so, so, so, so if we really tackle consciousness,
per se, the end of the terms of the hard problem, I don't, I don't, that, that isn't
necessarily going to be groundable in engineering, right? That aspect of the cognition is,
but actual consciousness per se, you know, for, first person
perspective, I'm not sure that that's groundable in engineering.
And I think specifically what's different about, what's
different about it is there's a, there's a couple things. So,
so let's, you know, here we go. I'll say, I'll say a couple
things about, about consciousness. One, one, one thing is that
what makes it different
is that for every other aspect of science,
when we think about having a correct or a good theory of it,
we have some idea of what format
that theory makes predictions in.
So whether those be numbers or whatever,
we have some idea, we may not know the answer,
we may not have the theory, but we know that when we get the theory
Here's what it's going to output and then we'll know if it's right or wrong
For actual consciousness not behavior not neural correlates, but actual first-person consciousness
If we had a correct theory of consciousness or even a good one
What the hell would what format would what it make predictions in right because because all the things that we know about
Basically boil down to observable behaviors
So the only thing I can think of when I think about that is is is
It'll be poetry or it'll be it'll be it'll be something to
If if I ask you okay, you've got a great theory of consciousness and here's this here's this creature
Maybe it's a natural and maybe it's an engineer and whatever.
And I want you to tell me what your theory says about this, this, this, this beings, what
it's like to be this being.
The only thing I can imagine you giving me is some piece of art, poem or, or, or something
that once I've taken it in, I share, I, I, I, I now have a similar state as whatever. That whatever. That's about as good as I can come up with.
Well, it's possible that once you have a good understanding of consciousness, it would be mapped
to some things that are more measurable. So, for example, it's possible that a conscious being is one that's able to suffer.
So you start to look at pain and suffering.
You can start to connect it closer to things that you can measure that in terms of how they
reflect themselves in behavior and problem solving and creation and attainment of goals, for
example, which I think suffering is one of the life of suffering. It's one of the big
aspects of the human condition. And so, if consciousness is somehow a, maybe at least a catalyst for suffering.
You could start to get like echoes of it and you start, you start to see like the actual
effects of consciousness and behavior that it's not just about subjective experience, it's
like it's really deeply integrated in the problem solving a decision making of a system, something
like this, but also it's possible that we realize
this is not a philosophical statement.
Philosophers can write their books.
I welcome it.
You know, I take the touring test really seriously.
I don't know why people really don't like it when a robot convinces you that it's intelligent.
I think that's a really incredible accomplishment and there are some deep sense in which that is intelligence.
If it looks like it's intelligent, it is intelligent.
And I think there's some deep aspect of a system that appears to be conscious.
In some deep sense, it is conscious.
At least for me, we have to consider that possibility.
And a system that appears to be conscious
is an engineering challenge.
Yeah, I don't disagree with any of that.
I mean, especially intelligence, I think,
is a publicly observable thing. And, and, and I mean, you know, science fiction is dealt with this for a century or
or much more, maybe this idea that when you are confronted with something that just doesn't
meet any of your typical assumptions. So you can't look in the skull and say, oh, well,
there's that frontal cortex. So then I guess we're good, right? If it's, if it's, you know,
so the thing lands on your front lawn
and this, you know, the little door opens
and something trundles out and it's sort of like, you know,
kind of shiny and aluminum looking and it hand you this,
you know, it hand you this poem that it wrote while it was
on, you know, flying over and how happy it is to meet you.
Like, what's going to be your criteria, right?
For whether you get to take it apart and see what makes
a tick or whether you have to, you have to be nice to it and whatever.
All the criteria that we have now and the people are using and as you said, a lot of people
are down on the touring test and things like this.
What else have we got?
Because measuring cortex size isn't going to cut it in the broader scheme of things. So I think this is a wide open problem.
That we are our solution to the problem of other minds. It's very simplistic. We give
each other credit for having minds just because we sort of on anatomical level, we're
pretty similar. And so that's good enough. But how far is that going to go? So I think
that's really primitive. So I think I think I think it's a major
unsolved problem. It's a really challenging direction of thought to the human race that
you talked about, like embodied minds. If you start to think that other things other than
humans have minds, that's really challenging because all men and created equals starts
being like, all right, well, we should probably treat not just cows with respect,
but like plants and not just plants, but some kind of organized conglomerates of cells in a peacher dish. In fact, some of the work
we're doing, like you're doing, and the whole community of science is doing biology, people
might be like, we were really mean devices.
Yeah.
I mean, yeah, the thing is, you're right, and I get, I certainly get phone calls about people
complaining about frog skin and so on.
But I think we have to separate the sort of deep philosophical aspects of the versus what
actually happens.
So what actually happens on earth is that people with exactly the same anatomical structure
kill each other on a daily basis, right?
So so we did.
I think it's clear that simply knowing that something else is equally or maybe more
cognitive or conscious than you are is not a guarantee of kind behavior, that much we know of.
So then, and so then, then we look at a commercial farming of mammals and various other things.
So I think on a practical basis long before we get to worrying about things like frog skin, we have to ask ourselves
why are we, what can we do about the way that we've been behaving towards creatures which
we know for a factor because of our similarities are basically just like us.
That's kind of a whole other social thing, but fundamentally, of course, you're absolutely
right in that.
We are also thinking about this.
We are on this planet in some way incredibly lucky.
It's just dumb luck that we really only have
one dominant species.
It didn't have to work out that way.
So you could easily imagine that there could be a planet
somewhere with more than one equally,
or maybe near equally intelligent species.
And then, but they may not look anything like each other, right? more than one equally or maybe near equally intelligent species.
And then, but they may not look anything like each other, right?
So there may be multiple ecosystems where there are things of similar to human-like intelligence.
And then you'd have all kinds of issues about, you know, how do you relate to them when
they're physically not like you at all?
But yet, you know, in terms of behavior and culture and whatever, it's pretty obvious
that they've got as much on the ball as you have. like you at all, but yet, in terms of behavior and culture and whatever, it's pretty obvious
that they've got as much on the ball as you have. Or maybe imagine that there was another
group of beings that was on average, 40 IQ points lower. We're pretty lucky in many ways. We don't really have even though we still act badly in many ways. But the fact is, all humans are
more or less in the same range, but the same, that same range, but it didn't
have to work out that way.
Well, by I think that's part of the way life works on earth, maybe human civilization
works is it seems like we want us ourselves to be quite similar.
And then within that, you know, whatever it is about the same relative to the IQ intelligence, problem
solving capabilities, even physical characteristics. But then
we'll find some aspect of that that's different. And that
seems to be like, I mean, it's really dark to say, but it seems to be the,
I'm not even a bug, but like a feature of the early development of human civilization. You pick the other, your tribe versus the other tribe in you war.
It's a kind of evolution in the space of memes, a space of ideas, I think, and you
war with each other. So we're
very good at finding the other, even when the characteristics are really the same. And
that's right. I don't know what that, I mean, I'm sure so many of these things echo in
the biological world in some way.
Yeah. There's a fun experiment that I did. My son actually came up with this. So we
did a biology unit together. He was so homeschool with this, so we did a biology unit together.
He used to use a homeschool, and so we did this a couple of years ago. We did this thing where
imagines you get the slime mold, right? Faisar and polycephalum, and it grows on a
petri dish of agar, and it sort of spreads out. And it's a single cell, you know,
produce, but it's like this giant thing. And so you put down a piece of oat, and it wants to go
get the oat, and it sort of grows towards the oat.
So what you do is you take a razor blade
and you just separate the piece of the whole culture
that's growing towards the,
oh, you just kind of separate it.
And so now, think about the interesting decision-making
calculus for that little piece.
I can go get the oat
and therefore I won't have to share those nutrients
with this giant mass over there. So the nutrients per unit volume is gonna be amazing. I should go eat the out and therefore I won't have to share those nutrients with this giant mass over there.
So the nutrients per unit volume is going to be amazing.
I should go eat the out.
But if I first rejoin, because if I start once you cut it, it has the ability to join
back up.
If I first rejoin, then that whole calculus becomes impossible because there is no more
me anymore.
There's just we and then we will go eat this thing.
So this interesting, you can imagine a kind of game theory
where the number of agents isn't fixed
and that it's not just cooperated defect,
but it's actually merge and whatever, right?
So that kind of, that competition,
how does it do that decision making?
Yeah, so it's really interesting.
And so empirically, what we found is that it tends to merge first,
it tends to merge first, and then the whole thing goes.
But it's really interesting that that that that calculus, like, do we even have, I mean,
I'm not an expert in the economic game theory and all that, but maybe there's a calumny,
some sort of hyperbolic discounting or something.
But maybe, you know, this idea that the actions you take not only change your payoff, but
they change who or what you are.
And that you may not, you could take an action
after which you don't exist anymore
or you are radically changed
or you are merged with somebody else.
Like that's, you know, as far as I know,
that's a whole, you know,
we're still missing a formalism
for even knowing how to model any of that.
Do you see evolution, by the way,
as a process that applies here on Earth,
or is it some, where did evolution
come from? Yeah. Yeah. So this thing that from the very origin of life that took us today,
what the heck is that? I think evolution is inevitable in the sense that if you combine, and
basically, I think one of the most useful things that was done in early computing, I guess in the 60s, it started with evolutionary computation and just showing how simple it is that
if you have imperfect heredity and competition together, those two things were three things,
right?
So heredity, imperfect heredity and competition or selection, those three things, and that's
it.
Now, now you're off to the races, right?
And so that can be, it's not just on Earth because it can be done in the computer, it can
be done in chemical systems, it can be done in, you know, Lee Smallens, as it works on,
you know, cosmic scales.
So I think that that kind of thing is incredibly pervasive and general.
It's a general feature of life. It's interesting
to think about, you know, the standard thought about this is that it's blind, right, meaning
that the intelligence of the process is zero. It's stumbling around. And I think that
back in the day when the options, with the options where it's dumb like machines or it's smart like humans.
And of course, the scientists went in this direction
because nobody wanted creationism.
And they said, okay, it's gotta be like completely blind.
I'm not actually sure, right?
Because I think that everything is a continuum.
And I think that it doesn't have to be smart
with foresight like us,
but it doesn't have to be completely blind either.
I think there may be aspects of it.
And in particular, this kind of multi-scale competency might give it a little bit of look ahead,
maybe, or a little bit of problem solving sort of baked in, but that's going to be completely
different in different systems. I do think it's general. I don't think it's just on Earth. I think
it's a very fundamental thing. It does seem to have a kind of direction that is taking us.
That's somehow perhaps is defined by the environment itself.
It feels like we're headed to or something.
Like we're playing out a script that was just like a single cell defines the entire organism.
It feels like from the origin of Earth's self,
it's playing out a kind of script.
Yeah.
You can't really go any other way.
I mean, so this is very controversial,
and I don't know the answer,
but people have argued that this is called
rewinding the tape of life, right?
And some people have argued,
I think Conway Morris
maybe has argued that it is that there's a deep attractor, for example, to human, to the human
kind of structure, and that if you were to rewind it again, you'd basically get more or less
the same thing. And then other people have argued that, no, it's incredibly sensitive to frozen
accidents. And then once certain stochastic decisions are made downstream,
everything is going to be different.
I don't know.
I don't know.
We're very bad at predicting attractors
in the space of complex systems, generally speaking.
We don't know.
So maybe evolution on Earth has these deep attractors.
That no matter what has happened, pretty much,
would likely end up there or maybe not.
I don't know.
What's a really difficult idea to imagine that if you ran Earth a million times,
500,000 times you would get Hitler.
Like, yeah, we don't like to think like that. We think like because at least maybe in America,
you like to think that individual decisions can change the world.
And if individual decisions can change the world, then surely any perturbation results
in a totally different trajectory.
But maybe there's a, in this competency hierarchy, it's a self-correcting system.
That's just ultimately, there's a bunch of chaos that ultimately is leading towards something like a super intelligent, artificial intelligence system. That's just ultimately, there's a bunch of chaos that ultimately is leading towards
something like a super intelligent, artificial intelligence system that answers 42.
I mean, there might be a kind of imperative for life that it's headed to. And we're too
focused on our day-to-day life of getting coffee and snacks and having sex and getting
a promotion at work, not to see the big imperative of life on Earth that it's headed towards
something.
Yeah, maybe, maybe.
It's difficult.
I think one of the things that's important about Kymica by engineer technologies all of those things are that we have to start
Developing a better science of predicting the cognitive goals of composite systems
So we're just not very good at it, right? We don't know if if if I create a composite system
And this could be internet of things or swarm robotics or a cellular or a cellular swarm or whatever. What is the emergent intelligence of this thing? First of all,
what level is it going to be at? And if it has goal-directed capacity, what are the goals going to be?
Like, we are just not very good at predicting that yet. And I think that it's a existential level
need for us to be able to, because we're building these things all the time. We're building physical structures like swarm robotics and we're building social financial
structures and so on, with very little ability to predict what sort of autonomous goals that
system is going to have, of which we are now cogs. And so, right, so learning, learning to predict and control those things is going
to be critical. So, in fact, so if you're right, and there is some kind of a tractor to
evolution, it would be nice to know what that is, and then to make a rational decision of
whether we're going to go along or we're going to pop out of it or try to pop out of it,
because there's no guarantee. I mean, that's the other, you know, kind of important thing.
A lot of people, I get a lot of complaints
from people emailing and say, you know,
what you're doing, it isn't natural, you know,
and I'll say, look, natural, that'd be nice
if somebody was making sure that natural
was matched up to our values, but no one's doing that.
I've a solution optimizes for biomass, that's it.
Nobody's optimizing, it's notizes for biomass. That's it.
Nobody's optimizing.
It's not optimizing for your happiness.
It's, I don't think necessarily it's optimizing for intelligence or fairness or any of
that stuff.
I'm going to find that person that emailed you, beat them up, take their place, steal everything
they own and say, now this is natural.
This is natural.
Yeah, exactly.
Because it comes from an old worldview
where you could assume that whatever is natural,
that that's probably for the best.
And I think we're long out of that garden of Eden kind of view.
So I think we can do better.
I think we have to, right?
We natural just doesn't great for a lot of life forms.
What are some cool synthetic organisms
that you think about,
you dream about, you think about embodied mind.
What do you imagine?
What do you hope to build?
Yeah.
On a practical level, what I really hope to do is to gain enough
of an understanding of the embodied intelligence of the organs and tissues,
such that we can achieve a radically different regenerative medicine
so that we can say, basically, and I think about it as,
in terms of like, okay, what's the goal,
kind of end game for this whole thing?
To me, the end game is something that you would call
an anatomical compiler.
So the idea is you would sit down in front of the computer
and you would draw the body or the organ that you wanted. Not molecular
details, but like, this is what I want. I want a six-legged frog with a propeller on top, or I want
a heart that looks like this, or I want a leg that looks like this. And what it would do if we knew
what we were doing is put out, convert that anatomical description into a set of stimuli
that would have to be given to cells to convince them to build exactly that thing.
I probably won't live to see it, but I think it's achievable.
And I think what that, if we can have that, then that is basically the solution to all
of medicine except for infectious disease.
So birth defects, traumatic injury, cancer, aging,
degenerative disease.
If we knew how to tell cells what to build,
all of those things go away.
So those things go away.
And the positive feedback spiral of economic costs
where all of the advances are increasingly more heroic
and expensive interventions of a sinking ship
when you're like 90 and so on, right?
All of that goes away because basically instead of trying to fix you up as you, as you're
degrade, you progressively regenerate, you apply the regenerative medicine early before
things degrade.
So I think that that'll have massive economic impacts over what we're trying to do now,
which is not at all sustainable.
And that's what I hope, I hope that we get it.
So to me, yes, the xenobots will be doing
useful things, cleaning up the environment, cleaning out
your joints and all that kind of stuff.
But more important than that, I think we can use
these synthetic systems to develop a science of detecting
and manipulating the goals of collective intelligence as of cells, specifically for regenerative medicine.
And then sort of beyond that, if we sort of think further beyond that, what I hope is
that kind of like what you said, all of this drives a reconsideration of how we formulate
ethical norms.
Because this old school, so in the old days,
what you could do is,
as you were confronted with something,
you could tap on it, right?
And if you heard a metallic clanging sound,
you'd said, ah, fine, right?
So you could conclude it was made in a factory,
I could take it apart, I can do whatever, right?
If you did that and you got in the sort of squishy
kind of warm sensation, you'd say,
ah, I need to be more or less nice to it,
and whatever, that's not gonna be feasible. It was never really feasible, but it was good
enough because we didn't have any, we didn't know any better. That needs to go. And I think that
by breaking down those artificial barriers, someday we can try to build a system of ethical
norms that does not rely on these completely contingent facts
of our earthly history, but on something much deeper that really takes agency and the
capacity to suffer and all that takes that seriously.
The capacity to suffer and the deep questions I would ask of a system is can I eat it and kind of sex with it, which is the two fundamental
tests of, again, the human condition. So I can basically do what Dolly does in the physical
space. So print out like a 3D print, Pepe the frog with the propeller head propeller head is the dream.
Well, I want to, I mean, I want to get away from the 3D printing thing because that will be available for some things much earlier.
I mean, we can already do bladders and ears and things like that because it's micro level control, right?
When you 3D print, you are in charge of where every cell goes.
And for some things that, you know, for, for like this thing, they had that, I think 20 years ago,
or maybe literally that, you could do that.
So yeah, I would like to have says the Dalai part
where you provide a few words and it generates a painting.
So here you say, I want to frog with these features,
and then it would go direct a complex biological system
to construct something like that.
Yeah, the main magic would be, I mean, I think from looking at Dali and so on,
it looks like the first part is kind of solved now where you go from the words to the image,
like that seems more or less solved.
The next step is really hard.
This is what keeps things like CRISPR and genomic editing and so on.
This is what limits all the impacts for a general medicine.
Because going back to, okay, this is the knee joint that I want or this is the eye that
I want.
Now, what genes do I edit to make that happen?
Going back in that direction is really hard.
So instead of that, it's going to be, okay, I understand how to motivate cells to build
particular structures.
Can I rewrite the memory of what they think they're supposed to be building such that then I can take my hands off the wheel
and let them do their thing.
So some of that is experiment, but some of that may be AI can help to just like with protein
folding.
That's exactly the problem that protein folding in the most simple medium, Trident has solved with the alpha fold,
which is how does the sequence of letters result
in this three dimensional shape?
And you have to, I guess it didn't solve it
because you have to, if you say I want this shape,
how do I then have a sequence of letters?
Yeah, the reverse engineer stuff is really tricky.
It is. I think where we're and we're doing some of this now is to use AI to try and build actionable
models of the intelligence of the cellular collectives. So try to help us, help us gain models that
that that and and we've had some success in this. So we did something like this for repairing birth defects
of the brain in frog.
We've done some of this for normalizing melanoma,
where you can really start to use AI to make models of how
would I impact this thing if I wanted to given all the
complexities and given all the controls that it knows how to do.
So when you say regenerative medicine, so we talked about creating biological
organisms, but if you regrow a hand, that information is already there, right?
The biological system has that information.
So how does regenerative medicine work today?
How do you hope it works?
What's the hope there?
Yeah.
Yeah.
How do you make it happen?
Well, today, there's a set of popular approaches.
So one is 3D printing.
So the idea is, I'm going to make a scaffold of the thing
that I want.
I'm going to seed it with cells.
And then there it is.
So kind of direct, and then that works for certain things.
You can make a bladder that way or an ear, something like that. The other ideas is some sort
of stem cell transplanted to the ideas. If we put in stem cells with appropriate factors, we can
get them to generate certain kinds of neurons for certain diseases, so on. All of those things are
good for relatively simple structures, but when you want an eye
or a hand or something else, I think, and this may be a non-popular opinion, I think the
only hope we have in any reasonable kind of timeframe is to understand how the thing
was motivated to get made in the first place.
So what is it that made those cells in the beginning create a particular arm with a particular set of sizes
and shapes and number of fingers and all that?
And why is it that a salamander can keep losing there
and keep re-growing there?
And a plenary can do the same.
Even more so.
To me, kind of ultimate regenerative medicine
was when you can tell the cells to build
whatever addition you need them to build, right?
And so the so that we can all be like,
plenary of basic.
Do you have to start at the very beginning
or can you do a shortcut?
I don't think you're already got the whole organism.
Yeah.
So here's what we've done, right?
So we've more or less solved that in frog.
So frogs, unlike salamanders,
do not regenerate their legs as adults.
And so we've shown that with a very
kind of simple intervention.
So what we do is there's two things.
You need to have a signal that tells the cells what to do,
and then you need some wave delivering it.
And so this is work together with David Kaplan,
and I should do a disclosure here.
We have a company called Morphaceuticals, and it's been off where we are trying to address
regenerated, you know, limb regeneration.
So we've solved it in the frog, and we are now in trials and mice.
So now we're going to border in mammals.
Now I can't say anything about how it's going, but the frog thing is solved.
So what you do is after-
You can have a little frog loose cowaco with every growing hand.
Yeah, basically, yeah. So what you do is we did with every growing hand. Yeah, basically.
Yeah.
So what you do is we did with legs instead of forearms and what you do is after amputation,
normally they don't regenerate.
You put on a wearable bioreactor.
So it's this thing that goes on and Dave Kaplan, those lab makes these things.
And inside, it's a very controlled environment.
It is a silk gel that carries some drugs, for example, eye-on-channel
drugs. And what you're doing is you're saying to these cells, you should regrow what normally
goes here. So that whole thing is on for 24 hours, and you take it off, you don't touch
the link again. This is really important because what we're not looking for is a set of
micro management, you know, printing or controlling the cells. We want to trigger.
We want to interact with it early on and then not touch it again because we don't know how
to make a frog leg, the frog nose out of make a frog leg.
So 24 hours, 18 months of leg growth after that without us touching it again.
And after 18 months, you get a pretty good leg.
That kind of shows this proof of concept that early on when the cells, right after injury,
when they're first making a decision about what they're going to do, you can impact them.
And once they've decided to make a leg, they don't need you after that.
They can do their own thing.
So that's an approach that we're now taking.
What about cancer suppression?
That's something you mentioned earlier.
How can all of these ideas help with cancer suppression?
So let's go back to the beginning and ask what cancer is.
So I think asking why there's cancer is the wrong question
I think the right question is why is there ever anything but cancer so so in the normal state you have a bunch of cells that are all cooperating towards a large scale goal.
If that process of cooperation breaks down and you've got a cell that is isolated from that electrical network that lets you remember what the big goal is, you revert back to your unicellular lifestyle.
As far as nothing about that border between self and world, right?
Normally when all these cells are connected by gap junctions into an electrical network,
they are all one self, right?
They meaning that their goals, they have these large tissue level goals and so on.
As soon as a cell is disconnected from that, the cell is tiny, right?
And so at that point, and so people,
a lot of people model cancer cells
as being more selfish and all that.
They're not more selfish.
They're equally selfish,
just that they're selfish smaller.
Normally the cell is huge,
and now they got tiny little cells.
Now what are the goals of tiny little cells?
Well, proliferate and migrate to where of life is good.
And that's metastasis,
that's proliferation of metastasis.
So one thing we found, and people have noticed years ago, that when cells convert to cancer,
the first thing they see is they close the gap junctions.
And it's a lot like, I think it's a lot like that experiment with the slime mold, where
until you close that gap junction, you can't even entertain the idea of leaving the collective
because there is no you at that point, right?
Your mind melded with this with this whole other network
But as soon as the gap junction is closed now the boundary between you now now the rest of the body is just outside environment to you
You're just you're just a a unicellular organism on the rest of the body's environment so
So we so we studied this process and we worked out a way to
Art officially control the bioelectric
state of the cells to physically force them to remain in that network.
And so then what that means is that nasty mutations like K-RAS and things like that, these
really tough oncogenic mutations that cause tumors.
If you do them, but then artificially control the bioelectrics,
you greatly reduce tumor genesis or normalized cells
that had already begun to convert you basically,
they go back to being normal cells.
And so this is another much like with the plenary,
this is another way in which the bioelectrics state
kind of dominates what the genetic state is.
So if you sequence the you know if
you sequence the nucleic acid you'll see the k-rass mutation you say well that's gonna be a tumor
but there isn't a tumor because because biorelectically you've kept the cells connected and they're
just working on making nice skin and kidneys and whatever else. So so we've started moving that to
to human glioblastoma cells and we're hoping for, you know, a patient in the future interaction with patients.
So is this one of the possible ways
in which we may quote cure cancer?
I think so. Yeah, I think so.
I think the actual cure, I mean, there are other technology,
you know, immune therapy, I think it's a great technology.
Chemotherapy, I don't think is a good technology.
I think we gotta get off of that.
So chemotherapy just kills cells?
Yeah, well chemotherapy hopes to kill more of the tumor cells than of your cells. That's
it. It's a fine balance. The problem is the cells are very similar because they are
your cells. And so if you don't have a very tight way of distinguishing between them,
then the toll that chemo takes on the rest of
the body is just unbelievable.
And immunotherapy tries to get the immune system to do some of the work.
Exactly.
I think that's potentially a very good, very good approach.
If the immune system can be taught to recognize enough of the cancer cells, that's a pretty
good approach.
But I think our approach is in a way more fundamental, because if you can keep the cells harness towards organ level goals as opposed to individual cell goals,
then nobody will be making a tumor or metastasizing and so on.
So we've been living through a pandemic.
What do you think about viruses in this full, beautiful, biological context we've been talking about. Are they beautiful to you?
Are they terrifying? Also, maybe let's say, are they, since we've been discriminating this whole conversation,
are they living? Are they embodied minds? Embodied minds that are asked holes. As far as I know, and I haven't been able to find this paper again, but somewhere I saw
in the last couple of months, there was some paper showing an example of a virus that actually
had physiology.
So there was something was going on.
I think proton flux or something on the virus itself.
But barring that, generally speaking, virus is a very passive.
They don't do anything by themselves.
And so I don't see any particular reason to attribute much of a mind to them.
I think they represent a way to hijack other minds, for sure, like cells and other things.
But that's an interesting interplay, though. If they're hijacking other minds,
the way we were talking about
living organisms that they can interact with each other and have it alter each other's
trajectory by having interacted. I mean, that's a deep, meaningful connection between a
virus and a cell. And I think both are transformed by the experience and so in that sense both are living
Yeah, yeah, you know the whole category that I
I
This question of what's living and what's not living? I really I'm I'm not sure and I know there's people that work on this
I want to I don't want to piss anybody off, but I have not found that particularly useful
as to try and make that a binary kind of distinction. I think level of cognition is very interesting
as a continuum, but living and non-living, I don't really know what to do with that. I don't
know what you do next after making that distinction. That's why I make the very binary distinction.
Can I have sex with it or not?
Can I eat it or not?
Those are actionable, right?
Yeah.
Well, I think that's a critical point that you brought up
because how you relate to something
is really what this is all about, right?
As an engineer, how do I control it?
But maybe I shouldn't be controlling it.
Maybe I should be, you know,
can I have a relationship with it?
Should I be listening to its advice? Like,, maybe I should be, you know, can I have a relationship with it? Should I be listening to its advice?
Like, like, all the way from, you know,
I need to take it apart, all the way to,
I better do what it says,
because it seems to be pretty smart
and everything in between.
Right, that's really what we're asking about.
Yeah, we need to understand our relationship
to it. We're searching for that relationship,
even in the most trivial senses.
You came up with a lot of interesting terms. We've mentioned some of them, agential material. That's a really
interesting one. That's a really interesting one for the future of computation and artificial
intelligence and computer science and all of that. There's also, let me go through some of them. If they spark some interesting thought
for you, there's telephobia, the unwarranted fear of airing on the side of too much
agency when considering a new system. Yeah, I mean, that's the opposite. I mean, being
afraid of maybe anthropomorphizing the thing. This will get some people ticked off, I think, but I don't think, I think the whole notion
of anthropomorphizing is a holdover from a prescientific age where humans were magic and everything
else wasn't magic.
You were anthropomorphizing when you dared suggest that something else has some features
of humans.
I think we need to be way beyond that.
And this issue of anthropomorphizing, I think,
is it's a cheap charge.
I don't think it holds any water at all,
other than when somebody makes a cognitive claim.
I think all cognitive claims are engineering claims, really.
So when somebody says this thing knows,
or this thing hopes, or this thing wants,
or this thing predicts, all you can say is fabulous. Give me the engineering protocol that you've
derived using that hypothesis. And we will see if this thing helps us or not. And then we
can make a rational decision.
I also like anatomical compiler, a future system representing the long-term end game of the science of morphogenesis that
reminds us how far away from true understanding we are.
Someday you will be able to sit in front of an anatomical computer, specify the shape
of the animal or plant that you want, and it will convert that shape, specification
to a set of stimuli that will have to be given to cells to build exactly that shape, no matter
how weird it ends up being, you have total control.
Just imagine the possibility for memes in the physical space.
One of the glorious accomplishments of human civilizations is memes in digital space.
Now, this could create memes in physical space. I am both excited and terrified
by that possibility. Cognitive light cone, I think we also talked about the outer boundary
in space and time of the largest goal a given system can work towards. Is this kind of
like shaping the set of options? It's a little different than options. It's really focused on, so back in this,
I first came up with this, back in 2018,
I wanna say, we had a, there was a conference,
a Templeton conference where they challenges
to come up with frameworks.
And I think actually it's the,
here, it's the diverse intelligence community
that-
Summer Institute.
Yeah, they had a Summer Institute, but-
The logo is the B with some circuits.
Yeah, it's got different life forms.
And, you know, so the whole program is called diverse intelligence, and they challenge
to stick them up with a framework that was suitable for analyzing different kinds of intelligence
together, right?
Because the kinds of things you do to a human, you are not good with an octopus, not
good with a plant, and so on So, so I started thinking about this and I asked myself what
what do all cognitive agents, no matter what their provenance, no matter what their
architecture is, what do cognitive agents have in common? And it seems to me that what they
have in common is some degree of competency to pursue a goal. And so what you can do then is you can draw. And so
what I what I ended up drawing was this thing that it's kind of like a like a backwards
minkowski cone diagram where all of space is collapsed into one axis and then here and then
time is this axis. And then what you can do is you can draw for any creature, you can semi-quantatively estimate
what are the spatial and temporal goals that it's capable of pursuing.
So for example, if you are a tick and all you really are able to pursue is maximum or a bacteria
in the maximizing the level of some chemical in your vicinity, that's That's all you've got. It's a tiny little like on.
Then, then you're a simple system like a tick or a bacteria.
If you are something like a dog, well, you've got some ability to care about some spatial
region, some temporal, you know, you can remember a little bit backwards.
You can, you can predict a little bit forwards, but you're never, ever going to care about what happens in the next town over four weeks or now.
It's just as far as we know, it's just impossible for that kind of architecture.
If you're a human, you might be working towards world peace long after your death, right?
So you might have a planetary scale goal that's enormous, right?
And so, and then there may be other greater intelligence is somewhere that can care in the linear range about numbers of creatures that you know,
some sort of Buddha-like character that can like care about everybody's welfare, like really
care the way that we can't. And so, and so that it's not a it's not a mapping of what you can sense,
how far you can sense, right? It's not a mapping of where how far you can act. It's a mapping of
how big are the goals you are capable of envisioning and working towards. And I think that enables you to put
synthetic kinds of constructs, AIs, aliens, swarms, whatever on the same diagram.
Because we're not talking about what you're made of or how you got here. We're talking about
what are the size and complexity
of the goals towards which you can work.
Is there any other terms that pop into mind
that are interesting?
I'm trying to remember, I have a list of them somewhere
on my website.
Target morphology, yeah.
Yeah, definitely check it out.
More of a more facutical.
I like that one.
I honest, sootical.
Yeah, yeah.
I mean, those refer to different types
of interventions in the regenerative medicine space.
So more of a suitor is something that it's a kind of intervention
that really targets the cell's decision-making process
about what they're going to build.
And I honestly recalls are like that,
but more focused specifically on the bioelectrics.
I mean, there's also, of course,
biochemical, biomechanical, who knows what else,
you know, maybe optical kinds of signaling systems there as well.
Target morphology is interesting.
It really, it's designed to capture this idea
that it's not just feed forward emergence
and oftentimes in biology.
I mean, of course, that happens too,
but in many cases in biology,
the system is specifically working towards a target in anatomical morphous space, right?
It's a navigation task, really.
These kind of problems solving can be formalized as navigation tasks and that they're really
going towards a particular region.
How do you know?
Because you deviate them and then they go back? Let me ask you because you've really challenged a lot of ideas and biology and the work you
do probably because some of your rebelliousness comes from the fact that you came from a different
field of computer engineering.
You give advice to young people today in high school or college
that are trying to pave their life story, whether it's in science or elsewhere, how they
can have a career that can be proud of or a life that can be proud of advice?
Well, it's dangerous to give advice because things change so fast, but one central thing
I can say, moving up and through academia
and whatnot, you will be surrounded by really smart people. And what you need to do is be
very careful at distinguishing specific critique versus kind of meta advice. And what I mean
by that is, if somebody really smart and successful and obviously competent is giving you specific
critiques on what you've done, that's gold. That's an opportunity to hone your craft to get
better at what you're doing to learn, to find your mistakes, like that's great. If they are telling you
what you ought to be studying, how you ought to approach things, what is the right way to think about things, you should probably ignore most of that.
And the reason I make that distinction is that a lot of really successful people are very
well calibrated on their own ideas and they own field in their own area and they know
exactly what works and what doesn't and what's good and what's bad, but they're not calibrated on your ideas.
So the things they will say, this is a dumb idea, don't do this and you shouldn't do that.
That stuff is generally worse than useless.
It can be very demoralizing and really limiting. And so, so what I say to people is read very broadly, work really hard, know what you're
talking about, take all specific criticism as an opportunity to improve what you're doing,
and then completely ignore everything else.
Because I just tell you, from my own experience, most of what I consider to be interesting
and useful things that we've done,
very smart people have said, this is a terrible idea. Don't do that. Just, I think we just don't know.
We have no idea beyond beyond our own like at best, we know what we ought to be doing. We very
rarely know what anybody else should be doing. Yeah, and their idea is their perspective has been
also calibrated not just on their field
in specific situation, but also on a state of that field, in a particular time in the
past.
So, there's not many people in this world that are able to achieve revolutionary success
multiple times in their life.
So, whenever you say somebody very smart, usually what that means is somebody who's smart who achieved the success
at certain point in their life and people often get stuck in that place where they found success
to be constantly challenging your worldview is a very difficult thing.
So yeah, and also at the same time probably if a lot of people tell
that's a weird thing about life. If a lot of people tell you that something is stupider is not going to work, that either means
that stupid is not going to work or it's actually a great opportunity to do something new.
And you don't know which one it is. It's probably equally likely to be either.
Well, I don't know the probabilities. Depends how lucky you are. Depends how brilliant you are.
But you don't know. And so you can't take that advice as actual data. Yeah.
You have to, um, you have to, and this is, this is kind of hard and fuzzy. It's like hard to describe and fuzzy.
But I'm a firm believer that you have to build up your own intuition. So over time,
right, you have to take your own risks that seem like they make sense to you and then learn from
that and build up so that you can trust your own gut about what's a good idea even when, and sometimes
you'll make mistakes and it'll turn out to be a dead end, and that's fine, that's science. But,
you know, what I tell my students is life is hard and science is
hard and you're going to sweat and bleed and everything. And you should be doing that for
ideas that really fire you up inside and really don't let the common denominator of
standardized approaches to things slow you down
So you mentioned Plenary being in some sense immortal. What's the role of death in life?
What's the role of death in this whole process we have is is it when you look about logical systems?
Is death an important feature?
especially as you climb up the hierarchy of competency?
Boy, that's an interesting question.
I think that it's certainly a factor that promotes change and turnover and opportunity
to do something different the next time for a larger scale system.
So app optosis, you know, it's really interesting.
I mean, death is really interesting in a number of ways.
One is like, you could think about, what was the first thing to die?
You know, that's an interesting question.
What was the first creature that you could say actually die?
It's a tough, it's a tough thing because we don't have a great definition for it.
So if you bring a cabbage home and you put it in your fridge,
at what point are you going to say it's died, right?
Then so that's it's kind of hard to know.
There's also there's there's one paper in which I talk about this idea.
I mean, think about this and imagine that you have a creature that's aquatic, let's say it's a frog or something, or a tapal, and the animal dies in the pond it dies for whatever reason.
Most of the cells are still alive. So you could imagine that if when it died there was some sort of breakdown of the connectivity between the cells. A bunch of cells crawled off.
They could have a life as amoebas.
Some of them could join together and become a xenobot
and twiddle around, right?
So we know from Plenary that there are cells
that don't obey the hayflick limit
and just sort of live forever.
So you could imagine an organism
that when the organism dies, it doesn't disappear
rather the individual cells that are still alive
crawl off and have a completely different kind of lifestyle and maybe come back together as
something else or maybe they don't.
So all of this I'm sure is happening somewhere on some planet.
So death in any case, I mean we already kind of knew this because the molecules we know
with something dies, the molecules go through the ecosystem.
But even the cells don't necessarily die at that point.
They might have another life in a different way.
And you can think about something like heala, right?
The heala cell line, you know, that has this,
that's had this incredible life.
There are way more heala cells now
that there have been, than there have been
the war when she was alive.
It seems like as the organ is become more and more complex,
like if you look at the mammals, their relationship with death becomes more and more complex.
So the survival imperative starts becoming interesting.
And humans are arguably the first species that have invented the fear of death, the understanding
that you're going to die.
Let's put it this way.
Long, so not like instinctual, I need to run away from the thing that're going to die. Let's put it this way. Like, long, so not like instinctual
like, I need to run away from the thing that's going to eat me, but starting to contemplate
the finiteness of life. Yeah. I mean, one thing, so one thing about the human light,
cognitive light cone is that for the first, as far as we know, for the first time, you might have
goals that are longer than your life's, but that are not achievable, right? So we know, for the first time, you might have goals that are longer
than your life's, that are not achievable, right? So if you're, if you were, let's say,
and I don't know if this is true, but if you're a goldfish and you have a 10-minute attention span,
I'm not sure if that's true, but let's say there's some organism with a short,
kind of cognitive light on that way, all of your goals are potentially achievable,
because you're probably going to live the next 10 minutes. So whatever goals you have,
they are totally achievable. If you're a human, you could have
all kinds of goals that are guaranteed not achievable because they just take too long,
like guaranteed you're not going to achieve them. So I wonder if, you know, is that, is
that a per, you know, like a perennial sort of thorn in our in our psychology that drives
some psychosis or whatever, I have no idea. Another interesting thing about that, actually,
and I've been thinking about this a lot in the last couple of weeks, this notion of giving up.
You would think that, evolutionarily, the most adaptive way of being is that you go,
you fight as long as you physically can, and then when you can't, you can't. And there's this video you can find of insects
crawling around where most of it has already gone
and it's still crawling.
Like Terminator style, right?
As far as as long as you physically can,
you keep going.
Mammals don't do that.
So a lot of mammals, including rats,
have this thing where when they think it's a hopeless situation, they literally
give up and die when physically they could have kept going.
I mean, humans certainly do this.
And there's some really unpleasant experiments that this guy forget his name did with drowning
rats where rats normally drown after a couple of minutes.
But if you teach them that if you just tread water for a couple of minutes, you'll get
rescued.
They can tread water for like an hour.
And so they literally just give up and die.
And so evolutionarily, that doesn't seem like
a good strategy at all evolutionarily.
So why would you, like, what's the benefit ever
of giving up?
You just do what you can.
And one time out of 1,000, you'll actually get rescued, right?
But this issue of actually giving up
suggests some very interesting metacognitive controls
where you've now gotten to the point where
survival actually isn't the top drive. And that for whatever, you know, there are other considerations
that have like taken over. And I think that's uniquely a mammalian thing, but then I don't know.
Yeah, the Camus. The existentialist question of why live just the fact that humans commit suicide
is a really fascinating question from an evolutionary perspective and what was the first and that's the other thing like what is the simplest
System whether whether evolved or you're natural or whatever that is able to do that right like you can think you know
What other animals are actually able to do that? I'm not sure maybe
You could see animals over time for some reason, lowering the value of survived
at all costs gradually until other objectives might become more important.
Maybe.
I don't know how evolutionarily how that gets off the ground.
That just seems like that would have such a strong pressure against it, you know. Just imagine a population with
a lower, you know, if you were a mutant in a population that had less of a survival
imperative, would your genes outperform the others? Is there such a thing as population
selection because maybe suicide is a way for organisms
to decide themselves that they're not fit for the environment somehow?
Yeah, that's a really, you know, population level selection is a kind of a deep controversial
area, but it's tough because on the face of it, if that was your genome, it wouldn't
get propagated because you would die,
and then your neighbor who didn't have that
would have all the kids.
It feels like there could be some deep truth there
that we're not understanding.
What about you yourself as one biological system?
Are you afraid of death?
To be honest, I'm more concerned with,
especially now getting older and having helped a couple of people
pass, I think about what's a good way to go, basically, like nowadays.
I don't know what that is.
Sitting in a facility that sort of tries to stretch you out as long as you can, that
doesn't seem good. And there's not a lot of opportunities to sacrifice yourself for something useful.
There's not terribly many opportunities for that in modern society.
I'm not particularly worried about death itself,
but I've seen it happen, and it's not pretty. I don't know what a better alternative is.
So the existential aspect of it does not worry you deeply, the fact that this ride ends.
No, it began, I mean, the ride began, right? So there was, I don't know how many billions
of years before that I wasn't around. So that's okay.
But isn't the experience of life?
It almost like feels like you're immortal because the way you make plans, the way you think
about the future.
If you look at your own personal, rich experience, yes, you can understand, okay, eventually
I died as people I love that have died.
So surely I will die and it hurts and so on.
But like, it sure doesn't, it's so easy to get lost
in feeling like this is gonna go on forever.
Yeah, it's a little bit like the people who say
they don't believe in free will, right?
I mean, you can say that, but when you go to a restaurant,
you still have to pick a soup and stuff, so, right?
So, so I don't know if I've actually seen that happen
at lunch with a well-known philosopher
and he didn't believe in free will
and the waitress came around and he was like,
well, let me see, I was like,
what are you doing?
You're gonna choose a sandwich, right?
So I think it's one of those things.
I think you can know that you're not gonna live forever,
but it's not practical to live that way.
Unless you buy insurance and then you do some stuff like that. But mostly, I think you just live
as if you can make plans. We talked about all kinds of life. We talked about all kinds of embodied
minds. What do you think is the meaning of it all?
What's the meaning of all the biological lives
we've been talking about here and earth?
Why are we here?
I don't know that that's a well-posed question
other than the existential question you posed before.
Is that question hanging out
with the question of what is consciousness
and their, uh,
heteroretreat somewhere?
Not sure because.
Sipping peanut colladas and because they're ambiguously defined.
Maybe I'm not sure that any of these things really ride on the, the correctness of our scientific
understanding, but I mean, just, just for an example, right?
I've always found it weird that people get really worked up
to find out realities about their bodies. For example, right? Do you see them?
X-mac, you know, you see that, right? And so this is great scene where he's cutting his hand to find out a piece full of cock. Now to me, right? If I open up and I find out in a fan budget cogs, my conclusion is not, oh crap, I must not have true cognition. That sucks. My conclusion is, wow,
Cogs can have true cognition. Great. So, right? So it seems to me, I guess I guess I'm with Descartes on this one that whatever the truth ends up being of
how is what is conscious and how it can be conscious. None of that is going to alter my primary experience,
which is this is what it is. And if a bunch of molecular networks can do it, fantastic. If it turns out
that there's a non-corporial, you know, so great, we can study that, whatever.
But the fundamental existential aspect of it is, if somebody told me today that you were
created yesterday and all your memories are fake, like Boltzmann brains and human skepticism
all that.
Okay, but here I am now.
So let's experience.
It's primal.
So like that's the, that's the thing that matters.
So the backstory doesn't matter.
I think so.
I think so.
From the first person per second now,
from a third, like scientifically,
it's all very interesting.
From a third person perspective,
I could say, wow, that's, that's amazing that,
that this happens and how does it happen and whatever. But from a first person perspective, I could care less. Like, I just,
it's just, well, what I've, what I learned from any of these scientific facts is, okay,
well, I guess then that's that, then I guess that's what is sufficient to, to, to give me my,
you know, amazing first person perspective. I think if you dig deeper and deeper and get a,
person perspective. I think if you dig deeper and deeper and get surprising answers to why the hell we're
here, it might give you some guidance on how to live.
Maybe, maybe.
I don't know.
That would be nice.
On the one hand, you might be right because on the one hand, I don't know what else could
possibly give you that guidance, right?
So you would think that it would have to be that or you would do it would have to be science because there isn't anything else.
So so that's so maybe on the other hand, I am really not sure how you go from any, you know, what they call from is to an ought, right?
From any factual description of what's going on.
This goes back to the natural, right?
Just because somebody says, oh man, that's completely not natural. It's never happened on Earth before. I'm not,
you know, impressed by that whatsoever. I think, I think whatever it has or hasn't happened,
we are now in a position to do better if we can't, right?
Well, this also, because you said there's science and there's nothing else,
there's science and there's nothing else. It's really tricky to know how to intellectually deal with a thing that science doesn't really understand. So, if you believe that science
solves everything, you can too easily in your mind think our current understanding, like we've
solved everything.
Right, right.
Right.
Right.
Right.
Right.
Right.
Right.
Right.
Right.
Right.
Right.
Right.
Right. Right.
Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. Right. more like the signs of today. Like, you can just look at human history and throughout human history,
just physicists and everybody would claim
we've solved everything.
Sure, sure.
Like, there's a few small things to figure out
and we basically solved everything.
Where in reality, I think asking,
like what is the meaning of life is resetting the palette?
Yeah.
Of like, we might be tiny and confused
and don't have anything figured out,
it's almost going to be hilarious a few centuries from now
when they look back at how dumb we were.
Yeah, 100% agree.
So when I say science and nothing else,
I certainly don't mean the science of today
because I think overall,
I think we are, we know very little. I think most of the things that we're sure of now
are going to be, as you said, are going to look at areas down the line. So I think we're
just at the beginning of a lot of really important things. When I say nothing but science,
I also include the kind of first person, what I call science that you do.
So the interesting thing about,
I think about consciousness and studying consciousness
and things like that in the first person
is unlike doing science in the third person
where you as the scientist are minimally changed
by it, maybe not at all.
So when I do an experiment, I'm still me.
There's the experiment, whatever I've done.
I've learned some things, that's a small change,
but overall, that's it. in order to really study consciousness,
you are part of the experiment.
You will be altered by that experiment, right?
And whatever is that you're doing,
whether it's some sort of contemplative practice
or some sort of psychoactive of whatever,
you are now your own experiment and you are right.
And so I fold that in. I think that's part of it. active of whatever, you are now your own experiment and you are right.
So I fold that in.
I think that's part of it.
I think that exploring our own mind and our own consciousness is very important.
I think much of it is not captured by what currently is third person science for sure.
But ultimately I include all of that in science with a capital S in terms of like a a rational investigation of both first and third person
aspects of our world.
We are our own experiment as beautifully put.
And when two systems get to interact with each other,
that's a kind of experiment.
So deeply honored, you would do this experiment with me today.
Thanks so much.
Thank you. I'm a huge fan of your work. Likewise.
Thank you for doing everything you're doing.
I can't wait to see the kind of incredible things you build.
So thank you for talking to me.
Really appreciate being here. Thank you.
Thank you for listening to this conversation with Michael Levin.
To support this podcast, please check out our sponsors in the description.
And now let me leave you with some words from Charles Darwin in the origin of species from the war of nature from famine and death the most
exalted object which were capable of conceiving namely the production of the
higher animals directly follows there's grandeur in this view of life,
with it's several powers having been originally breathed into a few forms, or into one, and that,
while this planet has gone cycling on according to the fixed laws of gravity, from a so simple
beginning, endless forms, most beautiful and most wonderful have been and are being
evolved.
Thank you for listening and hope to see you next time.
you