Pints With Aquinas - DEBATE: God's Existence - Trent Horn Vs. Alex O'Connor
Episode Date: August 1, 2020Trent Horn debates Alex O'Connor (@CosmicSkeptic) on God's existence. 🔴 ABOUT TRENT AND ALEX Alex's Youtube Channel: https://www.youtube.com/user/alexjoconnor Trent's Youtube Channel: https://www.y...outube.com/user/trhorn100 🔴 SPONSORS Hallow: https://hallow.com/mattfradd Catholic Woodworker: https://catholicwoodworker.com/ Use promo code mattfradd 🔴 LEARN MORE 🙏 Become a Patron of Pints With Aquinas: https://www.patreon.com/mattfradd 💻 Learn more about Pints With Aquinas: https://pintswithaquinas.com/ 🔴 APOLOGETICS CONFERENCE https://www.virtualcatholicconference.com/earlyapologetics2020 🔴 DEBATE FORMAT Opening Statements Affirmative Opening Statement (15 minutes) Negative Opening Statement (15 minutes) First Rebuttals Affirmative First Rebuttal (7 minutes) Negative First Rebuttal (7 minutes) Second Rebuttals Affirmative Second Rebuttal (4 minutes) Negative Second Rebuttal (4 minutes) Cross-Examination The cross-examiner is allowed to interrupt and move the flow of the argument as he sees fit. Affirmative cross-examines negative (12 minutes) Negative cross-examines affirmative (12 minutes) Audience Questions (30 minutes) Each person gets 2 minutes to answer a question addressed to them and their opponent gets 1 minute to respond Closing Statements Affirmative Closing Statement (5 minutes) Negative Closing Statement (5 minutes)
Transcript
Discussion (0)
Thank you. Thank you. All right, g'day, g'day, and welcome to Pints with Aquinas.
My name is Matt Fradd.
This is the very first debate we're hosting on this channel,
which I'm really excited about.
We'd like to actually host monthly debates here,
like this one between Trent and Alex.
So if you like that idea, do us a favor and support the channel by subscribing.
I just found out that we have our
second debate locked and loaded and you don't know who that is yet but at the end of this debate
I'm going to announce what that is about. Before we pull up Alex and Trent I want to say a big
thank you to the guys over at the Catholic Woodworker for helping to
support this show
so if maybe you're out there and you're an atheist
and after this debate once you become
a Catholic you can go
that's me being playful of course
but who knows you can go over to catholicwoodworker.com
take advantage of these
beautiful rosaries I don't like the rosaries
that are too big because they kind of like bruise you when you sit down, but most rosaries are super dainty. But these are just beautiful, very sacred looking, very manly. So go check them out. The Catholic Woodworker. He actually supports me on Patreon. Awesome guy. Family business. TheCatholicWoodworker.com is a place you want to go to get the best rosaries imaginable. Catholicwoodworker.com. All right,
let's pull up Alex and Trent. Hello, Alex and Trent. Hello, Matt. How's it going? It's going
well. Why don't we begin? I want to have the two of you introduce yourselves, maybe a minute each,
and then I'll lay out the format for today's debate. Why don't you start, Trent?
Sure. Well, my name is Trent Horn. I'm a staff apologist at Catholic Answers.
I have master's degrees in theology, philosophy, and bioethics, and I've authored nine books.
And at Catholic Answers, I explain and defend the Catholic faith.
I also host my own podcast called The Council of Trent, and if you're Catholic, you'll get
the pun, or at least if you're well-educated, you'll get the pun.
C-O-U-N-S-E-L, of course.
If you want to check that out, you can see it on iTunes, Council of Trent, or you can support it
at trenhornpodcast.com. I'm married to my lovely wife, Laura. I have two wonderful little boys at
home and a third on the way in September. Thanks very much, Trent. Alex.
My name is Alex. I'm a YouTuber, as much as I hate that label, but I'm also studying
for a degree in philosophy and theology at St. John's College, Oxford University.
I think these days people tend to introduce me more as a vegan advocate than a philosopher of religion, but that's kind of old hat to me.
It's what I've been doing for the longest time. It's been a while since I've done one of these debates.
But yeah, I'm not married. I don't have any children, but I'm here for the
ride and I'm looking forward to it. It's great to have both of you. I mean,
obviously being a Catholic myself, I agree with Trent, but I admire Trent. I admire you, Alex.
You do a great job explaining your position. So it's really an honor to have both of you on the
show. All right, why don't we begin? I just want to let everybody know the format of today's debate
and then we'll jump right into it.
We're going to have opening statements, 15 minutes each. Then we will have first rebuttals, seven minutes each.
Then second rebuttals, which will take four minutes. Then we'll have cross-examination for 12 minutes.
And then we'll have audience questions. So if you're watching live here on YouTube, be sure to stick around because we're going to be taking your questions. And when we do get a question, each
person gets two minutes to answer a question addressed to them, and then their opponent will
get one minute to respond. And then we will wrap up with closing statements of five minutes each.
I have a timer right here, and so I'll be timing them. You're welcome, of course,
to time yourself, but why don't we begin with you, Trent, correct? Sure. You're okay? That's good.
We'll start with 15 minutes. I'll let you know. Three, two, and go.
Sure. Well, Matt, before we start, actually, could you let everyone know the topic of the debate?
Thank you. That's probably a good idea. My understanding is that we are going to be debating veganism, Trent. I don't know if you knew that.
No, we're going to be debating, I believe, God's existence. So Trent is going to be making the positive case.
And then I believe, and you can correct me if I'm wrong, Alex, that you'll be critiquing that case.
Perhaps that's more accurate than saying you'll be critiquing that case.
Perhaps that's more accurate than saying you'll be making a case for atheism,
but feel free to interject.
That's about right, although I'm trying to make things a little bit more interesting than that,
so then we'll see.
All right.
Yeah.
Have I forgotten anything else?
I don't think so.
Did I mention that I'm vegan?
He's a vegan, apparently.
All right, so Trent, are you ready?
I am.
Start whenever you like.
Okay.
Well, I'd like to thank Matt for hosting this debate and Alex for agreeing to participate in it.
So in this debate, I want to ask nine yes-no questions
and then show that the answers to those questions
lead to a cause of the universe that has the traditional divine attributes,
or what most people call God.
So let's get started. Number one, does the universe have an the traditional divine attributes, or what most people call God. So let's get started.
Number one, does the universe have an explanation for its existence?
We know some objects in the universe are contingent, or their existence must be explained by something
else.
This debate exists because of computers and internet connections.
We pray you stay up.
The devices you watch it on exist because of factories and power sources.
All of these
things are contingent, or they don't explain their own existence. Instead, they must be explained by
something else. So how do we explain them? One way would be to posit an infinite chain of contingent
things explaining each other, but that doesn't explain why the whole series of things exists
any more than an infinitely long chain could explain how a chandelier is
hanging above my head. You could also say that an object's existence doesn't need to be explained,
but this violates the principle of sufficient reason, or PSR, which says things have a reason
for why they exist. We should believe this principle is true because if it were false,
we would expect unexplainable events like objects popping into and out of existence
without a cause to happen more often, or to put it more accurately, to happen at all.
Science relies on PSR being true because otherwise we could never rule out the conclusion
that things we observe simply have no reason for why they exist. Finally, without PSR,
we couldn't explain negative states of affairs. For example, it does not make sense to ask at
this moment, why isn't Matt Fradd's hair on fire? But it would make sense to ask that question if a
blowtorch were hitting his scalp and his hair remained unburned. Both cases presuppose that
things which exist must have reasons for why they exist, and they don't exist for no reason at all.
But the explanation for the
contingent things we observe cannot be another contingent thing. So it must be something beyond
the universe or the entire collection of contingent things that explains why everything exists.
Number two, does the universe explain its own existence? No, because that would make the
universe a necessary thing or something that has to exist by its very nature. But there are no reasons to believe the universe is necessary, and many reasons to believe
it is not necessary. For example, the question, why is that triangle black, prompts an intelligible
answer, whereas the question, why does that triangle have three sides, merely deserves the
retort, because it's a triangle. But the question, why does the universe exist,
does not prompt the retort because it's a universe, since existence is not a necessary property of universes. It's more like the question, why is that triangle black,
which warrants an explanation beyond the thing that needs to be explained.
There are two other factors about our universe that count against it having necessary existence.
It's property of
change, and it's finite past. So let's start with change. Change occurs when a potential X becomes
an actual Y. This can involve intrinsic change like growth or extrinsic change like motion.
But no potential X can become an actual Y on its own any more than water can freeze itself,
or a train car could propel itself.
Instead, something like a freezer or a locomotive must actualize the potential for change in these
objects. But of course, those actualizers only change because something else actualized their
potential for change. Could an infinite series explain this kind of change? No. Just as an
infinitely long train of boxcars would sit
motionless without a locomotive, an infinite number of things that must be actualized by something
else would be changeless unless there was a cause of the series that is just pure actuality and had
no potential. Just as a locomotive pulls without being pulled, this instance of pure actuality
would actualize without being actualized by anything
else. And since the universe contains a mixture of potential and actual, it is not the purely
actual cause we're looking for. What about the universe's finite past? Something is necessary
only if it is impossible for it to not exist. But if the universe came into existence, then it can't
be necessary. It would instead stand in need
of an explanation for why it exists. One reason to believe the universe has not always existed
is because the past contains causal chains that explain objects and events in the present.
However, no past causal series that terminates in the present can be infinitely long because
that would lead to a contradiction. Consider Robert
Kuhn's paper passer thought experiment. Imagine beings called paper passers who exist at every
January 1st in the past. So there's one at January 1st, 2020, one at January 1st, 2019, and so on
into an infinite past. Their job is to receive a piece of paper from the passer who held it during
the year before them,
and to see if it's blank. If the paper is blank, then they write a unique number assigned to them
on it. If the paper they receive already has a number on it, however, then they just pass the
paper along to the next paper passer at the end of the year. Now here's the question. What number
is written on the paper given to the paper passer at January 1, 2020,
whose year will go downhill very quickly? There has to be some number written on it,
because if it were blank, then the 2020 paper passer would write his number on it.
But it can't be blank, because if it were, the 2019 paper passer would have written his number
on it. But the 2019 paper passer could not have written his number on it, because if the paper
were blank when he got it, the 2018 paper passer would have written his number on it, because if the paper were
blank when he got it, the 2018 paper passer would have written his number on it.
If there are an infinite number of paper passers, then we have a paradox.
There is a piece of paper that arrives in the present that isn't devoid of numbers,
but also can't have any particular number written on it.
And this isn't unique to this scenario.
Other thought experiments experiments like Thompson's
lamp or the grim reaper paradox show that objects cannot have infinite causal histories. This means
causal series must be finite in nature, and the first member of the series would have to be
uncaused. And since causal chains must be finite, this means the number of events before today must
be finite, and so time is finite. If the past is
finite, then our universe began to exist and would require an uncaused cause for its existence.
Notice that we are at an important juncture. We've seen the universe has an explanation for
its existence, and that explanation is not the universe itself. Instead, this explanation is
necessary, or it explains its own existence. It is uncaused because it is the source of all causes, and it is pure actuality because
it is the source of all change and motion in the universe.
What else can we know about this cause of the universe?
Number three, is this cause changeable?
No, for two reasons.
First, change only happens when potential is reduced to actual, but this cause is pure
actuality, so it can't change.
Second, since causal chains can't be infinite, this means there can't be an infinite series
of events.
Since change is an event, this means the first cause cannot be subject to such an event,
or it must be changeless.
Question four, is the cause temporal?
No, because time is how we measure change, and because the cause of the universe is changeless. Question four, is the cause temporal? No, because time is how we measure change, and
because the cause of the universe is changeless, it follows that it must be timeless as well.
Number five, is this cause material? No, for two reasons. First, we know the cause is changeless,
and matter is always changing, at least on the atomic and subatomic levels. Second, if the cause
is timeless, then it must also be spaceless or immaterial,
because to be in space is to be in time. Even if the cause were a simple thing with no proper parts,
it would still change in relation to other things or points in space, and so it can't be confined
to space just as it can't be confined to time. Number six, is the cause limited? No, because that
would contradict the cause being pure actuality.
To impose a limit on something would be the same as saying there is a potential for that thing
which the thing in question can never actualize. That means the cause's causal power could not be
limited, which is another way of saying the cause is all-powerful or there is nothing it can't do.
And if the cause can bring something into existence from nothing,
then there really is nothing it can't do if it can accomplish that feat.
Number seven, is the cause necessary? Yes, because if it were contingent, or if it depended on
something else in order to exist, then this cause would need an explanation for why it exists,
and our argument would start all over again. Also, because this cause is changeless,
it can't go out of existence, because going from being existent to non-existent is a temporal and
mutable process, and we know the cause of the universe is timeless and changeless. Moreover,
in being pure actuality, this cause would have no potential for non-existence, and so it could
not fail to exist. Question eight, is the cause personal? Yes,
and here are five reasons to think so. One, there are only two kinds of entities that exist,
concrete ones like two toy blocks, and abstract ones like the number two or the shape of a cube.
But unlike concrete objects, abstract objects like numbers and shapes have no causal power.
Therefore, the cause of the universe cannot be an abstract object like a number, but must be some kind of concrete object.
But we also know this cause must be an immaterial concrete object, and the only immaterial causal
reality we know of is some kind of mind, which means the cause must be personal in nature.
Two, there are only two kinds of explanations for physical phenomena, scientific ones and
personal ones. Scientific explanations consist of physical laws that describe matter-energy interactions.
For example, the scientific answer to the question, why is that pot boiling,
is that heat is agitating the water molecules and causing evaporation. The personal explanation
would involve an intention of an agent, like, the pot is boiling
because I wanted tea.
A universe beginning from nothing can't have a scientific explanation because a state of
nothingness lacks the matter, energy, and descriptive laws that make up those explanations.
Therefore, only a personal explanation of the universe remains.
Three, this cause of the universe explains the existence of not just material objects,
but also abstract objects like numbers, mathematical truths, and propositions.
But these entities only exist in the mind, and so if these objects have necessary existence,
then they must reside in a necessarily existing mind that is explanatorily prior to them. Moreover,
if this mind has no potentiality, then its knowledge of these truths could not be limited,
and so it must be all-knowing. Four, many atheists say they'd believe in God if they saw something
like an amputated limb healed through prayer. But this means that they would pick a divine
explanation for an event over simply saying the event has no cause whatsoever. But if our universe
came into being just as inexplicably as a healed, amputated
limb, then atheists should be consistent and conclude that the universe is a divine cause as
well. Five, our universe contains moral properties that only make sense if they have a transcendent
moral source. Now, morality only applies to persons, so if the cause of the universe is the
source of these moral properties, then it must be a supremely good person and not an amoral, impersonal force. Which brings us to my last question. Number nine,
is the cause of the universe good? By good, we mean in both the moral and non-moral sense of
that word. A car has a bad timing belt, not because the belt is disobedient, but because
it can't fulfill its purpose of synchronizing an engine's valves. It's bad because it lacks something it needs in order to act in accord with its nature.
And this is true not just for artificial objects, but also for natural ones like trees and animals.
Now, if the cause of the universe has no potential and is pure actuality,
then it must be good by definition.
That's because it wouldn't lack anything,
and so it cannot be bad in the non-moral sense of that word. But the cause is also morally good because it is the source of
objective morality, or what I call moral facts. Alex said in his debate with Frank Turek that
if objective morality or moral facts existed, then this would be a compelling argument for God.
So we can make an argument like this. If moral realism is true, then God exists. Moral realism
is true, therefore God exists. Moral realism is the view that human beings discover moral truths
and don't create them. Truths like rape is always wrong or all human beings have equal worth do not
depend on human beings for their existence. Alex seems to agree with premise one and other famous
atheists also agree.
For example, J.L. Mackey said of moral facts, they are most unlikely to have arisen in the ordinary course of events without an all-powerful God to create them. But why should we believe
these moral facts exist? Well, we are confident the external world is real and that other minds
exist simply because those things seem to be real. If moral truths like rape is always wrong
seem just as real, then the burden of proof is on the moral skeptic to show us why we should
think otherwise. Now, Alex has previously said these moral truths are the objective consequences
of subjective assumptions, like the goodness of increasing well-being. But if that's true,
then they aren't objective because they depend on precarious
assumptions we can and should challenge. For example, imagine we could genetically engineer
human fetuses so they grow up with a desire to be slaves whose source of happiness comes from
blindly obeying other people. That might cohere with the overall goal of promoting human pleasure
or well-being, but many people will rightly say
this is wrong because it contradicts a basic moral fact independent of that assumption, that we ought
to treat human beings with dignity and respect. So if you believe in moral facts, then you should
believe in all-powerful God created them. Second, human beings are morally responsible for their
actions. Alex says all physical events are determined by prior physical causes.
But if that's the case and we lack free will and arsonists and serial killers are just
as determined as lightning bolts and tigers, then it would be nonsensical to blame humans
for actions just as it'd be nonsensical to morally blame a hurricane.
Moreover, if punishment isn't something that's deserved, but rather something the state meets
out for the good of society,
the state could theoretically punish innocent people like a criminal's family members
if such an act reduced crime overall by deterring criminals who at least care for their family members.
But it's objectively true human beings are capable of being blamed,
and it's objectively wrong to intentionally punish innocent people.
This is something that only a divine foundation of morality could make sense to hold up moral realism. So when all these
arguments are seen as a whole, they form a strong case that there is a changeless, timeless,
immaterial, infinite, necessarily existing, all-powerful, all-knowing, and all-good cause
of the universe, or what most people refer to as God. Thank you very much, Trent.
Four seconds remaining.
That was pretty impressive.
Okay, Alex, are you ready for your opening statement?
Just about.
Let me get a timer as well, and I'm pretty much good to go.
I'll just hit go whenever you say.
Go for it.
All right.
Okay, well, yeah, thanks, Matt.
And thanks to Trent as well, of course,
for agreeing to do this debate.
I can't say I was too familiar with Trent's work
before I agreed to this,
but from what I can tell,
I think we'll make a good pairing.
We have a lot more in common than people might think.
For a start, we are both technically Catholics.
I was baptized.
I took communion. I was confirmed. I used to pray my rosary. I even served a brief stint as an altar boy. So I think I've had at least some experienced sailing, shall we say, before I another ship. I gave up my belief ultimately in Catholicism and God, but not for some other belief system. I won't even say that there is no God or that I believe
there is no God. I just think that the arguments in favor of that proposition remain wanting.
Still, I will offer one argument to suggest that there is reason to think that perhaps God does
not exist, for which I do have a burden of proof. But this is something of an overdetermination.
My mission here broadly is just to show that there isn't sufficient reason to accept the
proposition that God does exist, which basically means responding to Trent's arguments and
playing by his rules.
Some people might claim this doesn't technically make me an atheist because they think someone
who merely lacks belief is not an atheist.
But if so, then so be it.
My job today isn't to be an atheist, but to argue against Trent's assertion that God exists.
In the meantime, you can call me whatever you like. So the argument that I mentioned, the one that I just mentioned,
in my view, is not just an interesting consideration, but I think it is the single
biggest problem for Christian theism that exists. The biggest reason as well that's preventing me
from seriously entertaining theism. And that problem is the problem of animal suffering.
Now, since this is an opening statement and not a rebuttal, I'll lay this argument out first, my affirmative case, before responding to Trent's arguments
at a later stage. So the problem of evil is famously one of the trickiest issues
for theism, but it's almost always, as a reflection of our general philosophical
considerations, I think, completely anthropocentric. Frequently, the problem of evil doesn't just focus on humans instead of
non-humans, or not taking into consideration non-humans just as much, but it completely
neglects any mention of the suffering of non-humans at all. But let's start with humans.
The problem of evil, loosely, is this. I like to discuss the problem of suffering more than the
problem of evil per se, just because some people apparently think it's problematic for an atheist to talk about evil, as we've seen.
However, Christians and atheists can both agree on the simple fact that suffering exists.
And if suffering does exist, then the point is this.
Any religion which purports the existence of a loving God must demonstrate why the suffering in the world is justified.
And the problem is most difficult, I believe, not on the problem of moral evil, but so-called natural evil.
That is, suffering caused not by human free choice, like things like murder or rape, but rather by earthly events,
generally referred to, somewhat unfortunately perhaps, as acts of God. Earthquakes, tsunamis, natural diseases, etc.
The difficulty for the theist in cases such as these is not so much to say that they're justified,
but to say that these aren't evil at all, because they result from the natural order which God controls, not human action, and therefore must be
justifiably inflicted, making it not evil, but actually a demonstration of either justice or necessity.
That is to say, when an earthquake rips a child from her mother's arms,
this isn't something to bemoan, but to celebrate, when an earthquake rips a child from her mother's arms, this isn't
something to bemoan, but to celebrate, since all actions of God must be just. And so we would be
witnessing some expression of divine justice, presumably with some great post-mortal reward.
Now, Trent has previously, as I've seen, tried to flip the question on the atheist by simply saying
that it's possible that God has some morally sufficient reason for allowing
suffering to occur, and that I have to prove why this can't be the case. Perhaps suffering is
required to explain the existence of human free will. Perhaps some evil is required for higher
order goods, right? Like you can't have bravery without fear, for instance. But analyze this, right? The suggestion is that some
level of suffering or evil, however you want to frame it, is necessary in order to achieve some
other aim that God has morally sufficient reason to desire. Fine. But then the theist must contend
with the idea that if evil is somehow necessary, we must have exactly the right amount of evil in
the world. And this
is the most difficult implication for me to accept. If a loving God may need to allow suffering for
reasons of free will or higher order goods or personal development or whatever it may be,
this would still not permit God to allow gratuitous suffering, right? There couldn't be any more
suffering in the world than is strictly necessary because then that suffering wouldn't be necessary
for good to prevail. And this is supposedly why suffering exists in the first
place. But it must also be accepted that therefore God couldn't have allowed any less suffering to
exist, because if there could be any less suffering in the world, this would imply that the suffering
in the actual world, as it is, isn't in fact necessary, and that God therefore does allow
specifically unnecessary suffering,
that is, suffering for which there is no morally sufficient reason, or which goes beyond that
reason. So I think Trent either has to accept something of a best of all possible worlds
approach, that exactly the correct amount of evil exists in the world, or produce another or
supplementary justification for suffering. Now if we believe in this best of all possible worlds
approach, I think we arrive at absurdity. Intuitively, it seems easy to accept that there could,
in principle, be at least some less natural suffering in the world. And I don't just mean
because the suffering is so great, although this observation does have some force. When Candide
witnesses the great Libsyn earthquake of 1755 and the horrendous suffering that it entailed, Voltaire has him mutter to himself, if this is the best of all possible worlds, then what must the others be like?
But I want you to really consider the plight of animals on planet Earth. torture chambers we call factory farms, but consider a deer whose leg is trapped under a
fallen branch and starving to death in not just fear and agony, but also confusion. Is this a part
of the suffering that's necessary to obtain whatever God has morally sufficient reason to
desire? Could that deer have not have died five minutes earlier? Could its hunger not have been
marginally, just marginally reduced? Why should this proposed sufficient reason require
exactly this amount of suffering and no less? Why can't this deer be granted some form of mercy?
Why can't it being granted some form of mercy be compatible with whatever God apparently desires,
like free will or higher order goods or whatever it may be? Is it not compatible with the existence
of free will for this deer to have died 30 seconds before it did? And what good is this obtaining anyway?
Remember, I'm talking about natural evil here, not moral evil. How could this deer's agonizing
and unseen death be a necessary requirement for human free will or some higher order good or
something? Does it somehow help shape the moral character of those human beings who aren't even aware
that the deer is suffering and never find out that it did?
Does it somehow help the animal?
And if so, how exactly?
At least for humans, the religious expect
some kind of divine compensation
in the afterlife for their suffering.
But what does the deer get?
I imagine this deer, not to mention the 72 billion
land animals we slaughter each year,
not to mention the sea life we do the
same to, not to mention the many, many more animals that are killed by their natural environment.
I doubt these animals are going to experience the bodily resurrection promised to us by Jesus
Christ. So what exactly is the reward for their suffering? And why does that suffering need to be
exactly so high, exactly so ubiquitous and exactly so deep and so agonizing. Now, I'll remind you, this
suffering, this struggle for survival, this natural tragedy is exactly what we would expect
if we assume a naturalistic universe with no moral author and supervisor. I have no problem
explaining why animals have such a tragic capacity for suffering, but the religious have a harder
task on that point. If the proposed god of the universe is a God of justice, as Trent suggests, then I want to know what on earth these animals have done to deserve the treatment they receive.
So that's the first thing.
But we also, of course, have moral evil to contend with, along with natural evil. from a shop to the confinement and forced sterilization of Uighur Muslims in China,
or the billions of animals forced into gas chambers each year to suit our fondness for a
bacon sarnie. Of course, this one is famously easy. God is a God of love, and love must be
given freely. For humans to be truly free, they must be capable of committing horrendous evils
and inflicting masses of suffering. That is, a removal of suffering by God is metaphysically
incompatible with free will. And free will is more important than protection from suffering,
especially given the reward of the afterlife. And voila, theodicy. But I would like to pose
the same question to Trent as I pose to anyone else who has ever made this free will defense
in my presence and to which I've still never received a sufficient answer.
Is there free will in heaven? I would assume so, unless you think heaven is some kind of moral matrix in which we all robotically tend towards the good without freedom.
But a second question, do people in heaven have free reign to inflict suffering in the same way
they do on earth? I would assume not, unless you want to suggest that it's logically possible for someone to commit a racist holocaust or something in heaven, but that
they just choose not to. That seems absurd. Clearly in heaven there can't be such suffering. Maybe you
think there can, but that would be an interesting bullet to bite. But if heaven is a place in which
there is free will and yet no suffering, then this serves as a counter example to the claim
that free will requires the unrestricted ability of free
creatures to inflict suffering. If free will can exist without suffering also existing, the free
will defense becomes meaningless. If it can happen in heaven, it can happen on earth. But just to
change gears, another problem with free will defense is a problem with free will more broadly,
and that's this. I think that free will violates the principle that Trent relied on
so heavily in his opening statement, that is the principle of sufficient reason. The principle of
sufficient reason, I'll remind you, is the notion that anything which exists has a reason or
explanation for its existence. And the reason this is important is because the contingency
argument that we've just heard from Trent relies on this principle. Trent says, given that the
universe exists, there are only three options. Either the universe exists without explanation, it explains its own existence, or it's explained by
something outside of the universe, e.g. God. Now, Trent rejects the first of these options,
that the universe has no explanation for its existence. Why? Because of the principle of
sufficient reason, or the PSR, as I might call it for short as everything has an explanation for its existence
Or at least all contingent things the universe the universe is an
Existing thing and so it has an explanation right now why believe that the PSR is true
Well Trent argues along with people like Edward Fazer and many others that rejecting the principles sufficient reason can undermine our basic assumptions of science
Right science assumes that unexplained
phenomena always have some explanation just waiting to be found. If we don't accept that
everything has an explanation, as Trent has said, we could just assume things occur all the time for
no reason, and we have no reason to investigate them to discover why they occurred. But if the
principle of sufficient reason is true, then it would apply to every thought that exists in the human mind. Anytime you think something, there is an explanation, not just for why you thought
something, but why you had that particular thought and not another one. But okay, maybe the explanation
is internal. Maybe me having thought X is explained by the fact that I wanted to have thought X.
Fine, but if PSR is true, then there needs to be an explanation for why I wanted to have thought X. Fine, but if PSR is true, then there needs to be an explanation
for why I wanted to think thought X.
Maybe the reason is that I like thought X,
but that doesn't necessarily determine me to think it.
But if PSR is true,
then there must be a reason
why it did determine me to think it
in that particular case.
If every thought we ever have
is explained by a chain of reasons
explaining why that particular thought arose when it did, and in the way that it did,
that therefore morality can't exist, which we just heard Trent say in terms of the moral argument for God.
He says, you know, if there is if there is if there's this kind of causal chain of explanations for everything that exists, then morality disappears.
Well, I think that's exactly what the principle of sufficient reason
implies. And so I think you either have to throw out the principle of sufficient reason,
or you have to throw out morality on your own account, unless you can find some way to get
out of this objection, which I'll be interested to hear. Now, I've got about two minutes left,
but there's one other thing that I should point out, or at least plant a flag in that we can talk about, which is that it's been claimed by Trent at least once, and also by other people
who propose the principle of sufficient reason, that to deny the principle of sufficient reason
contradicts some basic fundamental ideas in science, as I've already said. But interestingly,
as recently as 2015, we have good reason to think that actually affirming the principle of sufficient reason is what undermines science.
I can talk about this more in my rebuttal stage, but the principle of sufficient reason
entails that there's no such thing as a random event.
A random event by definition occurs without an explanation for why it occurred in the
way that it did.
And so if there is randomness in the universe, then it's false that everything which occurs
has a fully sufficient explanation for its existence in the way that it exists. Famously, quantum mechanics seems,
appears to involve true randomness. I don't have time to fully explicate it here, but there's an
experiment you can perform sending two entangled subatomic particles to different detectors and
measuring the spin of one seems to instantaneously affect the spin of the other.
And because I really don't have time now, I'll explain why in the rebuttal stage.
But in 2015, it was finally conclusively proven that there can't be some hidden variable that
exists locally to the particles that explains this.
And there's a principle in quantum mechanics called local realism, which needs to be essentially denied on the basis of this experiment.
Localism being the idea that a particle can only be affected by something in its immediate vicinity, and realism being the idea that any result of an experiment has a real-world explanation for that experiment, for that result, which is essentially the principle of sufficient reason.
So we either have to deny locality or we have to deny realism. If we want to keep the principle
of sufficient reason, that is, we want to keep realism, we have to deny locality, which follows
from denying locality things such as causes being able to occur after their effects and a whole
other thing which seems to completely undermine science. And I'll explain why that is the case
in my rebuttal stage, if that's a line you want to go down. But I just want to plant a flag there to say that actually,
if you hold on to the principle of sufficient reason, the cost might be higher than you think
it is. But I think I've just run out of time. Yeah. Thank you so much, Alex. Okay, those were
our two opening statements. And now we're going to move into our first rebuttal period, where each
debater will get seven minutes. Trent, let me know when you're ready.
All right.
Go for it.
I'm ready.
Go for it.
Well, thank you, Alex, for that opening statement.
You are truly just as smart as you sound.
I wish I had a British accent, too.
So what points did Alex make saying that God doesn't exist? Well, he didn't show any logical arguments to show that God does not exist. He did offer some probabilistic arguments against the existence of
God and some problems with my own case. But we have to remember that probabilistic arguments
can't defeat a demonstrative argument for God's existence any more than circumstantial evidence
in a murder case can defeat something like an ironclad alibi that
shows someone is innocent. But there's also weaknesses in these probabilistic arguments that
show that they're not insurmountable. When it comes to the principle of sufficient reason,
randomness doesn't violate the principle of sufficient reason. Quantum events have probabilistic
causes rather than determinate ones. For example, if quantum mechanics did not act in accord with
the principle of sufficient reason, then scientists could never perform experiments with regularity
to make the very conclusions that Alex brought up. Also, Alex neglects that there's more than
one theory of quantum mechanics. For example, there's the Bohm-De Broglie interpretation,
which shows there are determinate causes in quantum mechanics, but through what are called hidden variables. Alex then offered us a long argument from evil against God. He talked about
what I call the why-not-heaven-now objection. So Alex claims that since it's logically possible
for free human beings to not choose evil in heaven, then God is morally obligated to only
allow those state of affairs to obtain. And I agree with him, there's going to be no evil in
heaven, either because God alters our wills somehow, or because when we are in the
presence of God, who is perfect goodness itself, our intellect will never fail to apprehend the
good. Well, the answer to the question is that a world where—so God can make a world without any
evil whatsoever that's like heaven, but a world where free people, where people make a free choice
to have a heavenly existence,
has more goods than one where they're merely created in that state.
You could analogize this analogy to marriage, for example, that it would be better for someone to marry the perfect spouse than to create someone in the state of being perfectly married,
like some kind of creepy Stepford wife.
In other words, a world that journeys from imperfection to perfection has more goods in it
than one that is already perfect. Now, Alex might object and say that the good of pleasure is all
that matters and these other goods that come about in pain aren't important, but that's a highly
controversial opinion. As I noted in my opening statement, if maximizing pleasure or well-being
is all that matters, why not genetically engineer fetuses to grow up to be slaves that
only want to improve well-being their whole lives? Or if pleasure is all that matters,
why not take them a fetus and put them in a pleasant virtual environment their entire life
as they grow up, like the Matrix, so they only know pleasure? I think many people would see that
as a harm, actually, and that it's better to have a real existence even if pain is a result from it.
Alex also brought up free will. Now, this is not a fatal objection to theism, because you could
just be a theist who doesn't believe in free will. You could be a theological determinist,
for example, like some Calvinists. But when it comes to free will, I would say that Alex claims
I can't claim whatever begins to exist happens without a cause, because don't people freely
choose to act? What's
causing them to make those choices? And I would say that they are causing themselves to make that
choice. I reject the view that human beings can't be their own cause for their events by making
a rational choice, and that if God exists, he can be capable of allowing them to be able to do that.
But here's the thing. Even if we can't fully explain how free will works, we know it does work in the same way an atheist can say consciousness emerges from matter,
even if he can't say how at this moment. And plus my argument for moral responsibility
shows that we do have free will because if free will didn't exist, you couldn't be morally
responsible for anything. So if you believe in moral responsibility, I don't see how you can hold that view and also deny that free will exists.
Now going on to evil. Christians do not claim natural evils like tsunamis are good things.
Rather, we would say the pain and death that they inflict are privations of goodness.
But since God is infinite in power and knowledge, he can allow these privations to exist in order
to create greater goods or prevent greater evils. What could those reasons be? Well, any finite physical system will
have fluctuations in goodness. The fire increases in being, and the brush decreases in being. The
lion increases in being, the zebra decreases when it's eaten. Pain is necessary for animals to
function in the natural world. Complex organisms can't last long if they don't feel pain. Goods like courage and compassion
cannot exist without evils like danger and suffering. And it's possible some theists believe
that God will compensate animals in the afterlife. The Bible does talk about the lion laying down
with the lamb, for example. Now, Alex said he found it implausible that our world contains the perfect amount of suffering, and I agree there is no such value. God could
always create a world with more or less suffering. It would just have more or less goods as a result.
But as long as God always brings more good from the evil he tolerates, there's no reason to believe
he does not exist. Alex also talked about that there's these unjustifiable evils, but I would
say, what criteria has he offered to show some evils are gratuitous and others aren't? He actually
hasn't done that. How much time do I have, Matt? I'm sorry. One minute and 42 seconds. Perfect,
there we go. Let's talk about animal suffering. Alex said we should doubt God's existence because
he doesn't see a justification for the suffering of non-human animals.
But as I said before, there could be goods to justify animal pain that exists.
And the existence of animals themselves, even if humans are not aware of them, may be that good.
I'll give you a thought experiment.
Imagine all human beings left Earth to colonize another planet.
And Alex is on the last ship leaving Earth.
There's only non-human animal life left on the Earth. And I said to him, Alex, here's an antimatter device that will instantly
destroy the Earth, instantly. The animals just phase out of existence. Should we do that,
or should we let these animals continue existing? If you say that they should continue existing,
even though there will be a lot of pain and suffering for those animals, if you think that
that is worthwhile, then there can be good reasons to justify the creation of allowing animals to
exist even though they may suffer. Otherwise, I think Alex would be committed to the view that
if we ever left the earth, we should just vaporize it right after we go. Finally, atheistic ethics
leads to an arbitrary preference of humans over animals or an unlivable equality that would make factory
farmers worse than Hitler. Atheists just can't explain the unique moral duty we have to animals,
and if that's an objective moral duty we have, i.e. it's just an objective fact we ought to
care for animals, but not in the same way that, as an objective fact, we ought to not cause unnecessary suffering for animals, but also a fact that humans are intrinsically more worth,
have more worth than animals, I believe only theism can explain the existence of those moral facts.
Okay. Thanks, Trent. And then we'll move on to Alex's first rebuttal. You ready, Alex?
Just about, yeah.
There's a hell of a lot to respond to. I mean so many doors are being opened
but let me try and go through. I've tried to make rough notes about this.
The first thing that you said there Trent was that quantum mechanics still acts in accordance
with kind of probabilistic explanation rather than deterministic explanation
but this doesn't make much sense because the very problem with quantum mechanics is that
Yes, if you fire enough photons, you'll find that 50% of the time they have up spin and 50% of the time they have down spin
But there is no way
To explain why any particular photon has either up spin or down spin. That's the point, right?
I I agree with you that there is an expert that there there's an explanation in the conditions from which the photons emerge, perhaps, that explains why they statistically exist in a 50-50 correlation.
But there is no explanation for why any particular photon has a particular spin.
And that's what was proven in 2015 by Bell's theorem.
This is the point that was proved.
It was previously thought, look, maybe it's the case that there's some kind of hidden variable.
Maybe that's the problem. As you say, there are multiple interpretations of quantum mechanics. But the
point that I would have raised or trying to raise before I ran out of time was that the interpretations
of quantum mechanics in which you're allowed to keep the principle of sufficient reason mean you
have to give up locality, right? You have to give up locality, which according to general relativity has wacky,
wacky corollaries, right? For instance, the idea that if information can travel faster than the
speed of light, which is true under this interpretation, then you can get, because
of the way that different frames of references affects the time in which something happens, depending on your frame of reference, a cause could occur after the effect.
So I don't disagree with you that there are interpretations of quantum mechanics which allow
you to keep the principle of sufficient reason, but at what cost? It would be at the cost of a
principle like causation or something which would undermine not just many other aspects of science,
but also a great many arguments for the existence of God.
But the point remains that it's not about explaining why there's a like.
Sure, there could be an explanation to say why 50 percent of the photons have this been a 50 percent have that's been.
But we need an explanation for why a particular photon has a particular spin.
And that's what can't be done. And that's why the principle of sufficient reason would be uh false um let me
see here i've got an interesting question actually you when you mentioned the the why not heaven now
objection you said that one of the reasons why perhaps uh we want a world of earthly suffering
before we reach heaven is because there's something morally better about freely choosing good than
just being kind of good by nature, right?
Like, sure, God could create beings in heaven which are just good because they're in the
presence of God and they know to be good and that's just their nature.
But it's morally superior to have the opportunity to commit evil, but to choose to choose to
commit good instead.
Right.
This is this is what you said of human beings. But if it's morally, if a being which
has the capacity to commit evil and chooses not to, is better than a being that's good by nature,
then I would imagine that your definition of God is not a maximally good being. Because if God is
a maximally good being, then I suppose he's not capable of committing evil. He's perfectly good
by nature. But you seem to be suggesting, or maybe he's capable of committing evil by some kind of roundabout way.
But you're saying you would imagine, I would imagine you would say that he's good by nature.
But if God is good by nature, you seem to imply in your discussion of humans that it's actually more moral, better morally speaking, to not be good by nature, but to choose to be good despite not being good by nature.
And I'm interested in how that would work out.
I'm sure you have an answer to it, but it's not something I've thought about before.
So I'd be interested to hear what you have to say.
You also said about evil being the privation of good, which I simply can't accept.
I can't imagine that the infliction of a Holocaust would just be the lack of suffering when trivially,
I don't think this is a neutral state of affairs.
I think that something like picking up a phone is a neutral state of affairs.
That's a privation of good and the privation of evil.
But the infliction of suffering, I don't think I can count as a privation of good.
But perhaps that's just where Catholic and utilitarian intuitions rub against each other.
But you did offer a thought experiment about animals saying, well, if we were leaving the
planet, would I kill every animal on on on on the place of the planet?
Now, that's a difficult question, right? Because I think
you need to take into consideration the distinction between doing and allowing.
I'm not quite sure what I'd do in that situation. Let's just say perhaps, you
know, I would kill those animals, like fine, but that's not the situation God's
in, right? The situation God's in is being offered an opportunity to
allow those animals to continue existing with less suffering, and if you gave me
that option, I'd choose that option any time. So I think you've presented something
of a false dichotomy by saying, look, we're getting on the spaceship and you have the
opportunity to allow these animals to carry on suffering as much as they are, or you kill them
all immediately. It's like there's a middle option, which is to have them experience less suffering.
middle option, which is to have them experience less suffering. Then what else do we have? You also made what I consider to be something of a bizarre statement about factory farmers being
worse than Hitler, on my view. I suppose because you interpret me as saying that non-human animals
are worth the same as human animals, and you think that the only way to justify a distinction there is with theism. I don't think
that's true. I think that if you have, say, a utilitarian worldview, which maybe broadly I do,
but it's not quite accurate, but let's just say that you did, you could easily say that because
humans are capable of experiencing higher and different kinds of pleasures, to say a pig,
that although a human's pleasure is worth the same as a pig's pleasure, all other things being equal, the human is worth more than
the pig because of that capacity for pleasure.
In other ways, there are ways to say that a human is worth more than the pig, and I
think a human is worth more than the pig.
But my position on animals in this instance isn't that animals are worth the same as humans,
it's that animals are worth more than human taste buds, right?
So I wouldn't say that factory farmers are worse than Hitler, because
you could, or at least you're not committed to that view, because you could say that if
animals are worth less, killing lots of animals for food is really, really, really bad. And
killing lots of humans, because they're Jews or disabled, is worse, right? Those are perfectly
compatible in my view. You've also, on the point about free will,
you said, well, look, you could just say the explanation for why a particular thought arises
is because, you know, the explanation is within you, like you are the explanation for your thought.
But look, there has to be an explanation for why you had that thought and not another thought,
right? We're not just trying to, the principle of sufficient reason doesn't just commit you to
offering an explanation for why a thought occurred, but why that thought occurred.
Otherwise, you haven't sufficiently explained, right?
To be a sufficient explanation, it has to explain everything.
So the question would become, why is it that you had that particular thought, right?
And if there's an explanation for that, it either exists within you, which requires its own explanation, or you get explanatoryily far enough back that it goes outside of you, external to you, in which case you're not
in control of it. So I think that that would undermine free will. That's seven minutes.
There's so many things to discuss, but I think that's about all I can just about kind of scrape
the surface there. Okay, thank you very much, Alex. We're going to now move into our second
rebuttals, where each of you will get four minutes.
Trent, are you ready? Yes. Start whenever you like. All right.
All right, let's start. This is really fun. I'm really enjoying this. This is a cheesecake of a
debate. You know, we've got a lot of stuff
packed in here. I think it's going to be great for people to pour over. So let me just comment
on the few things that Alex brought up. When it comes to quantum mechanics, and this goes a little
bit to the question about free will, the principle of sufficient reason that I was defending is a
limited principle of sufficient reason. I'm not arguing that any state of affairs or any event
requires an explanation.
It could be the case that you have something that happens that we can't determine, we can't predict.
You know, if you have a ball on the tip of an infinitely sharp cone, why does it roll right
instead of left? There may not be an explanation, or there may be an explanation that's probabilistic
that we can't determine. But when it came to the question of the de Broglie-Bohm hidden locality variables in
quantum mechanics, Alex brought up the Bell inequality theorem. But John Bell himself,
in speaking about this, said it is a merit of the de Broglie-Bohm version to bring this non-locality
out so explicitly that it can't be ignored. So he actually praised this interpretation of quantum
mechanics. But as I said, if you have a limited version of PSR where I'm talking about the reason a thing exists rather than a particular event takes place, then my argument from contingency
to a necessary being still holds up quite well.
When it comes to goods, Alex said, is it better for a being to be able to choose evil and
not good?
No, it's not better for that being, but the good is always better than evil. However,
beings that have free will, you can draw out more goods in that situation than beings that
lack free will. So beings that have free will, you can have moral free will, you can have goods
like forgiveness, mercy, compassion, courage. And it's worthwhile to create a world where we
have those goods during the
imperfect phase of that world's existence, and then they cease to exist when the world journeys
into its perfect phase of existence. So I don't see any contradiction there at all, that it's
better to—I think a world with these kind of virtues, and from our own experience we see
that virtues and compassion, these are goods, and if God makes a world where those goods exist,
he's perfectly free to do so. And when it comes to privation, my argument is that a privation is
not nothing. It's not invisible, it's not non-existent. For example, a hole in the ground
is a privation, but it's real, you can fall into it. So these privations are bad, but once again,
if God chooses to make a physical system where goods and privations are bad, but once again, if God chooses to make a
physical system where goods and privations can exist, as long as he brings more good from that,
then there's no moral problem here. When it comes to picking up a phone, for example,
that's not a privation of goodness. In fact, it's non-moral goodness that occurs there of the
ability of a rational creature to pick up something and make a call, that's actually a good of using irrational powers to reach out and call
someone and let them know whatever's happening.
When it comes to utilitarianism, I agree utilitarians can say that there are higher order pleasures,
but at the same time, it's interesting, I don't think atheism could justify, I'm sure
Alex would say, well, we can justify factory farming right now because we need it to at least feed the
world.
I've heard him say this before.
We might need some factory farming in order to feed people, and it's an evil we tolerate.
I wonder if Alex would say the same thing about human slavery or human sex trafficking.
I highly doubt he would be willing to make those similar tolerations, which bespeaks
to the view that human beings have an intrinsic kind of worth that animals do not. And I believe that atheism simply can't explain that, but theism can explain
that human beings remain in the image and likeness of God. Also, those higher-order pleasures, by the
way, not all humans can exercise them. Some humans are cognitively similar to or inferior to pigs,
like infants or unborn children. Under Alex's view, if those humans are valuable because they have the capacity for higher-order pleasures,
that would explain why infanticide is wrong,
but I'd say we got an argument against abortion pretty quickly here.
Finally, just to summarize everything,
what Alex has given us in his reply to this case
are puzzles about free will and puzzles about suffering,
but they have not disproven my argument for an unactualized actualizer, an uncaused cause, who has all the divine
attributes. He's offered puzzles that have not refuted demonstrative arguments."
Okay, all right, thank you Trent. And now we're going to move to
your second rebuttal for four minutes. Just let me know when you begin, I'll
just click the timer, okay? All right, Nice one Okay, some interesting points again, I'll try and blast through this as quickly as possible
Trent you made an interesting claim that your principle of sufficient reason is a limited one that doesn't necessarily apply to
Events this to me seems to be a distinction without difference
I'm not sure how you could justify that claim and why it wouldn't undermine science in the same way about events
I'm not sure how you could justify that claim and why it wouldn't undermine science in the same way about events
Requiring certain explanations, but if I just granted it to you that fine, okay, not all events need an explanation I could consider the Big Bang to be an event and
The event of the Big Bang is the explanation for why the universe exists
But on your account the event itself doesn't need an explanation
so the universe can come into existence without an explanation because that's an event. And it's the event that caused the existence of the universe.
And therefore everything's explained and there's no problem. The only way to avoid this objection,
I would say, is either to find some way to explain why specifically the Big Bang is one of the kinds
of events that would require a cause or to, I suppose, throw out the principle of sufficient
reason.
I hope you see what I'm saying there.
Also, you said that John Bell praised other interpretations of quantum mechanics.
Sure, John Bell's paper came out in 1964, right?
The proof that specifically got rid of the hidden variables theorem,
the hidden variables hypothesis, happened in 2015.
I've got no doubt that in the interim periods there was plenty of good reason to believe
either side, but it's only very recently that we've got good substantive evidence to say
that the hidden variables hypothesis of explaining Bell's inequalities is totally bunk.
And again, I don't exactly have time to explicate this here. And I'm certainly not a quantum physicist.
And I presume that you're not.
One of the benefits of studying at Oxford is that one of my good friends who I went for coffee with the other day,
who just received his master's in physics with the best grade in the whole university.
And I was able to talk to him for a very long time about quantum mechanics.
And I was bemused when I realized, because I'd been thinking about the principle of sufficient reason in preparation for this debate, and when I mentioned it in passing, he just blew my mind by showing me exactly how to hold on to the principle of sufficient reason is what undermines current scientific understanding, not the other way around.
You also said that I have elsewhere said that factory farming might sometimes be justified in order to sustain human civilizations, but I wouldn't make the same kind of concession for
something like human slavery. Again, I fear this is a misunderstanding of my position. I've said
that animals need to die in order for us to survive in one way or another, because even if
you're growing crops, you're killing insects, you're killing rodents and things. Sure, but the
difference is we don't need slavery in order to survive, but we need to kill animals in order to survive.
So, like, if there's a situation in which you actually need to kill an animal in order to survive, that suffering becomes necessary and you're justified in inflicting it.
There's not a situation in which slavery is actually necessary to human survival in the same way.
And that's why I think that the two aren't equivocated.
If you were in a situation where the only way for you to survive would be
to kill another human being i think that you're probably justified in doing that and it would be
a form of self-defense right so i do think that the analyses would be the same i think that perhaps
we would know i can see from your facial expression that we disagree with uh that you probably disagree
with me there but i think that uh human beings have a have uh how can i put this um an impossible
it's impossible not to have this drive to survive
for most people the people who do have it they can't help but have it and i think that like
the drive to survive there is a psychological fact that is true of anybody uh and and so
essentially the point that i want to make on that is that in order to say that somebody shouldn't
do something that is what is kind of allowing them to survive in order for somebody to
completely essentially self-destruct themselves um would be psychologically impossible and i think
because if ought implies can you shouldn't be able to ask them uh to do that um also uh well i mean
let's not open the the the the question of abortion we've got about four seconds and that's
definitely not time to answer
it. But I think I'm more pro-life than most pro-choices that I know. And I think I'm probably
more pro-life than you think I am, but that's not to say I am pro-life. But maybe that's a
discussion for another time. Okay. Well, one can hope. All right. So I just want to let everybody
know what's coming up here. We're
about to go into cross-examination, and then we will be taking your questions. Please remember,
as I said in the beginning, that at the end of this debate, I'm going to be announcing the next
debate and who those debaters will be on this channel. So please be sure to stick around to
that. But before we move into cross-examination, I want to say thank you to our second sponsor,
Halo. Halo is a really fantastic app that will help you pray and meditate. It's actually the
number one Catholic app in the US. It has five-star ratings on the App Store, and there's
really something for everyone there. So if you're somebody who's just beginning to pray,
then that's great. If you're somebody who prays every day, there's something there for you as well. You can listen to the rosary, the divine mercy chaplet, have nightly
examines, prayer, minute meditations. They even have sleep stories where people read the Bible
to you. I don't think anybody wants to hear me reading the Bible. One day there was this guy.
Nobody wants that. But Father Mike Schmitz is on this. That's pretty cool. It's free to download and it has permanently free content. But if you go to hallo.com slash Matt
Fradd, and we'll be sure to put that in the show notes below, you can get access to the whole thing,
30-day free trial, hallo.com slash Matt Fradd. Please check it out. I actually mean it. It's
a really sophisticated app and just, yeah, super great. So check it out.
Okay. So here's what we're going to do now. We're going to be moving on to cross-examination.
And I just want to let those viewing know how this is going to go.
First, we're going to begin with the affirmative cross-examine. And so that'll be Trent cross-examining Alex.
He has 12 minutes to do that. And then Alex will cross-examine. And so that'll be Trent cross-examining Alex. He has 12 minutes to do that.
And then Alex will cross-examine Trent. But I also want people to know that the cross-examiner
is allowed to interrupt and move the flow of the argument as he sees fit. So if Trent starts
cross-examining Alex or Alex-Trent and they feel like they're not going anywhere, it's not rude of
them to interrupt or anything like that. Okay. So Trent, you let me
know when you're ready and we'll begin with 12 minutes. Whenever you start speaking, I'll just
click the 12 minute timer. Sure. Yeah. Let's jump into this here. Alex, I'd like to talk about
the point actually, when you talk about the raised eyebrows, because I do think that
the different intrinsic moral worths of human beings as opposed to other animals is a significant
problem for atheism. You made the claim that, well, it's justified to kill non-human animals
if one needs to do that in order to survive, and we would do the same for human beings. Now,
I agree in the sense of self-defense, where if someone is trying to kill me, my intention is not to kill them. It's to stop
their fatal attack, even if I foresee it will kill them. It's the principle of double effect.
But I think it's very clear that you cannot kill another person merely to save your own life.
There was a famous British maritime case called R.V. Dudley versus Stevens in
1884. It was about a group of sailors who were stranded at sea. I was just about to bring this
up. Yes. Yeah. OK, good. You know about it. They killed and ate the cabin boy, Richard Parker,
which creepily enough, Edgar Allan Poe wrote a story about a cabin boy named Richard Parker
being eaten 60 years earlier. And the court said there that no, murder is not, necessity is not a defense for murder. So would you agree that in some cases,
just because you need to live, you don't have the right to kill another human being?
Well, interestingly, the reason that I was going to bring up that example was
to play on the intuition that they were actually justified in doing so, right? Because
these were men in a boat who were all about to die. They were going to die anyway, and they would be dead had they not committed this action. And the
cabin boy was ill. He was going to die anyway. And so they made that sacrifice. Now, don't
get me wrong. This is not a nice thing to do. It's not like a blasé, yeah, it's fine,
you know, you can survive.
But the cabin boy, the point of the case is the cabin boy didn't volunteer himself.
That's correct, yeah.
So he was murdered.
So I guess that there-
Depends on your definition of murder, I think.
Depends on your definition of murder, because I think-
The Crown has said in this case.
The legal definition of murder, yes, absolutely.
So even though others may see this as an unjustifiable homicide, you just might be the minority view
to dissent
against that.
I think it's at the very least a blurred case.
And I think that we can be quick to judge somebody in that situation for the action
they took.
But I think that if you're in that situation, I think there's a fair argument to be made
that it's a justifiable action to take.
Okay, well, let me change the situation a little bit.
Suppose you're dying and you need a heart transplant,
and there's someone who is also terminally ill that has a heart,
but the problem is they're probably going to live for another six or 12 months,
and you're going to kick the bucket in three months.
Even though that person's going to die anyways,
that wouldn't justify you killing them in order to take their heart
so that you can live on for many decades.
Whereas in almost all cases, we would be able to kill an animal for any reason to be able to live.
So it seems to me we still have a big difference between how we treat humans versus how we treat
non-humans that I don't think can be explained if your criteria for morality is species neutral.
Do you see the problem? I do see what you're saying. I think those situations are different,
and I wouldn't be in favor of people being able to harvest people's organs in that respect.
At least on first instance, one of the differences between these situations is that
we don't want terminally ill people being worried that their organs are going to be
harvested at a moment's notice, right. These situations are not the same.
True, but also, Alex, we might want passengers on ships to not be worried they'll be eaten in lifeboats.
I mean, this is true, but I think we can agree that this is such a rare occurrence that I don't think this is a this is exactly.
I mean, in other words, I don't think people are generally afraid that they're going to end up on a boat at sea that isn't going to be rescued and happen to be the person who's ill and about to die.
Well, that was that was true now.
That's true now. But it wasn't true 150 years ago.
That was quite common for people at that time.
Oh, I see.
I suppose that's a I don't know how common that would be at the time. I suppose that, that, that may be fair,
but it was kind of a dirty, it was a dirty secret of maritime travel that everyone tolerated until
the Dudley case. So I guess, let me, let's just, we'll put that there. I mean, morality is, I think
when we talk about this, morality is probably one of the most interesting things for people
to wrap their heads around. So we'll, we'll talk more about it. Uh, but let me actually, well,
things for people to wrap their heads around, so we'll talk more about it. But let me actually—well,
morality, evil, that kind of fits in there. Your argument from evil, it was a probabilistic one that you saw—it doesn't disprove God, but it makes him unlikely, because there's some evils
that you don't see how they could be justified, or they appear to be gratuitous. So is your
argument that it's the gratuitous evils that should make us skeptical of God or all the evils? It's just a subset of the evils. Is that correct?
Yeah, no, I definitely don't think that the existence of evil, perhaps I should frame it as suffering,
towards certain complications, is a problem in itself.
I think it's the extent and the depth of the suffering, and that's the point that I was trying to make by saying that
I believe that you would be actually committed, despite what you said in your rebuttal, to the view that we do have exactly the exact right amount of suffering in the world.
Because, look, I mean, if you want to, and bear in mind, my argument was specifically to respond to a defense of the existence of suffering.
So people who say that suffering exists because God has morally sufficient reason.
You said a second ago or a moment ago, you said that God could create more suffering or less suffering. There would just be
more or less good. But my understanding of a perfectly moral being is one which maximizes
morality, one which maximizes the good wherever it's possible to do so. Now, I understand why
you'd have a limitation on a maximally perfect being in getting rid of, say, all suffering.
That wouldn't make any sense. As you say, if there are such things as higher order goods or goods which require certain
suffering such as free will, then it makes perfect sense for God to allow those suffering.
Well, Alex, what I would say is I would disagree with that assertion that a perfectly
good being must maximize the good, that you and I would agree there is no such possible
world that has an intrinsic maximum of the maximum good, because you could
always make more and more people. And then you would lead to some kind of contradictions.
For example, suppose there was a world with 1 million people and they have, let's say,
99% happiness. Would you say that's a good world? Yeah, I see where you're going with this.
Well, let me just keep going because not everyone will be as clairvoyant as you.
So then what if we did 2 million people at 98% happiness?
Yeah, see, I don't know, of pleasure, uh, the amount
of pleasure that someone receives and the quantity of people receiving that pleasure
are on the same kind of pedestal here. For instance, I think that one person experiencing
two X suffering is worse than two people experiencing X suffering. Um, like I don't,
I don't think they kind of map onto each other in, in, in the same way.
Okay. So I'm trying to get a handle around what you would say.
Now, what's interesting here, though, is when we're talking about evil,
about the moral duty that God has, so if God creates a world, I'm trying to get my head around
for you. There's two questions here. What would be the contents of the moral duty? We can put that
in quotation marks. And then two would be the epistemic foundation—sorry, the ontological foundations, like where do these
moral duties come from? So like if God makes a world, is it just maximizing pleasure or is it
minimizing suffering? Like they could be incompatible. How would they be incompatible?
Well, for example, if the goal is just to minimize suffering, then God can make a world with an electron, and then there's zero suffering.
Right, yeah, I see what you mean.
So I think that generally speaking for conscious creatures that do exist, the minimization of suffering and the maximization of pleasure are
kind of two sides of the same coin, and some people prefer to frame it in terms of
maximization of pleasure, some people minimization of suffering. You could just say that you want a balance of both.
But look, I see minimization of suffering, you could just say that you want a balance of both.
But look, I see what you're saying, which is that there can't be, like, it's difficult
to imagine what the perfectly moral or the worst possible world would look like.
But my point is just this.
My point is that it seems almost trivially true that there could be at least some less
suffering in the universe.
And if there's not-
Sure, and I agree with you.
I agree with you.
And so I wonder what your reasoning would be or what your suggestion would be as to why it's not the case.
And what I would say to you is, can suffering be justified?
Yes.
Okay.
Okay, let me reframe then.
I think that there can be less unjustified suffering in the world than there is right now.
Then what criteria do you use to determine whether a suffering is justified or unjustified?
What objective criteria do you use I said to be clear? I'm I'm
Talking in terms of your world you here. So whatever you take to be the criterion of good
But I think either and and again you can reject this claim
So I'll say that whatever your criterion of good is I I'm asking the question, could there be less unjustified suffering?
And if the answer is yes, then I think you've run into a problem.
If the answer is no, then I think you've accepted the best possible world approach.
But Alex, under my view as a theist, I do not believe unjustified suffering exists at
all because I believe any suffering can be justified by greater goods or the prevention
of greater evils.
So on my view, I don't see that as a problem. But for you, if... That's precisely my point.
I mean, I would say that that's precisely the point that I made. Maybe we're talking
past each other here a little bit, but my point was to say that the theist believes that any
instances of suffering or what people would generally call natural evil are not in fact
evil at all. These aren't because they're not unjustified suffering. I don't hold that view. My view is that evil is a lack of good. There are
intrinsic evils, things that one must never do, but evil itself is just an absence of good. There
can be non-moral evil and moral evil. There can be moral evils that we tolerate and moral evils
that we must never tolerate or never engage in.
So it'd be a richer dichotomy here. Matt, how much time do I have?
Sorry about that, you have one minute and 50 seconds.
Okay, well let's go to the basement then of these, about morality and moral duties, because
my argument was if moral realism is true, God exists, moral realism therefore God.
My argument was if moral realism is true, God exists.
Moral realism, therefore God.
It's a valid argument.
And based on your comments in the debates, would you hold the premise one?
What the moral realism is true or that moral realism entails God.
If moral realism, then God.
I'm not sure about that because I don't think that I'm not a moralist.
I don't think that moral claims can be objectively true. And I think I would hold that that would be the case even if God existed.
So I'm not sure I can accept that claim. And I can explain why, if you'd like.
Okay. So you believe moral realism is simply an impossible state of affairs?
Depending on exactly what you mean by moral realism, for instance, I think that a claim like you ought not murder doesn't have truth value.
Okay, so it's just an utterance or disapproval of certain kinds of killing.
I would interpret it slightly differently, but essentially, yes.
It's essentially a form of emotivism or non-cognitivism, I guess you could say, but it's potentially a bit more complicated than that. So you would say that when it comes to morality, there are the statement
rape is always wrong, or let's take the most foundational one, the statement
humans ought to promote human flourishing. You don't believe those statements are true.
I think that perhaps a statement of something being good can be true because that's a descriptive
claim, but an ought claim contains an essence of command and commands can't have truth value.
So I don't think that can have truth value.
Okay.
I have no problem if there's a moral author of the universe and that God determines that
something is good, I think that's perfectly coherent.
However, I'm not sure I would say the same for ought statements,
which, in other words, have prescriptive
content. If it turned out, though,
there were...
Final question, 12 minutes are up, or should we...
We can switch.
That's fine. All right.
Just trying to be fair to both of you here.
Okay, so Alex, as soon as you start, I'll click
the 12-minute timer, and you can cross-examine
Trent, and you can interrupt him at any time to move the conversation along.
Sure.
Well, I'd be happy to further that discussion perhaps in another point because it takes 10 minutes just to get it off the ground because we have to understand exactly what we mean by different moral terms.
So I'm interested, just to be clear about this talking about animal
suffering i'm interested trent what do you think for example um okay well let me just put the
question like this why do animals suffer as much as they do in your view why do animals suffer the
current amount that they suffer yeah well i would say animals suffer the current amount that they suffer?
Yeah.
Well, I would say animals suffer the current amount that they suffer
because our universe has regular, fixed, and predictable laws of nature,
and that animals are finite physical creatures
that have to operate in that environment.
And so in order to operate as complex organisms,
the higher-order animals will need survive.
They survive best when they have pain sensors to determine threats to them.
And it allows their they evolve to have pain sensors to increase their ability to survive and propagate.
But it's my answer. It's at least possible that those animals could have experienced less suffering. Like,
do you think it's, in other words, what I'm asking is, am I expected to kind of interpret that as you think it would have been logically impossible for God to have created a functional
set of natural laws that didn't entail the amount and depth of animal suffering that it currently
does? No, I don't think it's logically impossible. I mean, you could create...
The reason I ask, sorry, is because if you say that the reason why this animal suffering
exists, or at least one reason, is because of the fact that there are natural laws which
entail it, well, if those natural laws aren't necessarily the case, then why not have just
made them differently?
That's not really a justification for the problem at hand.
Well, you didn't ask for justification.
You only asked a descriptive
question, why are things the way that they are? Okay, I suppose implicitly I mean to say,
why are they that way, assuming that there is a morally perfect supervisor of the universe?
Why would he allow that to occur? Well, for the same reason as the theist's overarching defense,
which would say that any evil and suffering, whether it's human or
non-human, an all-powerful being can allow the existence of evil if that being can bring greater
goods from it or prevent greater evils. That for me, it seems very clear that if this principle
applies to humans, that we do this all the time where we allow evil to exist and suffering among humans and non-humans
to secure certain greater goods. If we allow humans to do that in limited circumstances,
I don't see a problem in allowing an omnipotent, omniscient creator to have far more latitude to
do it. And also, the reasons he would have, I don't really have epistemic access to all of them,
because I'm a limited
finite creature. But given that it does work for humans, I don't see why it wouldn't work for God.
That was why I brought up that thought experiment about vaporizing the earth when humans leave.
I think many people would leave the earth as kind of a zoological habitat for those animals,
even knowing that they would suffer because there is a goodness just in them existing.
Well, unless you could create a system whereby they're existing with less suffering.
Like if you had that option, surely that would be the option to take.
Well, I mean, in other words, let me put it this way.
If I gave you that option, we're moving away in this spaceship and say, look, you've got
three options here, Trent.
You can either abolish all life on Earth as we move away from it.
You can keep things exactly as they are, or you can create a kind of paradisal Earth where animals are existing
with at least a lot less suffering, maybe no suffering, if you like.
Which button do you press?
Well, no suffering would be different.
The terms would be vague.
If there still is suffering, even minimal suffering, after millions of years, that would
be an incredible amount of suffering.
Okay, so let me put it this way then.
There's a button which reduces the amount of suffering by 50% overall.
With no kind of non-beneficial side effects, right?
With no kind of effects down the line that are going to make this worse.
My personal view on the matter is that I believe the existence of animals is a good thing.
So maybe I would push that button. Maybe I wouldn't. I might need more data as to what it
means to reduce the suffering. So for example, by pushing the button, it keeps everything the
way it is. I guess my trouble with this is that, yeah, it's possible to create a feasible world where it's the exact
same but there's less suffering.
My concern is that that may not be feasible.
It might be like the problem of philosophical zombies.
Yeah, sure.
So now you're toying with the idea that maybe the amount of suffering in the universe is
exactly where it needs to be.
And that's what I was putting forward in the first place, what I think your view commits
you to.
I think you either have to say that the amount of suffering in the universe cannot be budged one way or the other or you have to okay
Well, here's can we have good reason to say that it should go one way. Well, here's how I was here's how I'd answer that
Here's how I'd answer if I if I give you those buttons and you refuse to press the button or at least even can say
Well, I don't know what I put maybe I'll just let them go on suffering
Maybe I won't press this button which has no other effect but to give them less suffering
Like I think that would be I think that would be a moral travesty not to press that button.
But then, you agree though that the button that results in no suffering,
I'm not obligated to pick that because it ends the animal's existence. And you agree that's a harder case.
Well, yes, that's a harder case.
It may be the case that we should press that button if the suffering is bad enough and if the suffering isn't counterbalanced by pleasures.
Right.
Let's just say it's the way of this question.
Right.
But ultimately, what I would say is my choosing to push any of those buttons will be undergirded
by a particular I would say that it's not under your view that morality is about subjective
assumptions we have about what the good is.
I could just tell you, Alex, I have a different subjective assumption about the ultimate foundation of morality. I don't believe it's a utilitarian
maximization principle. So I'm not under a moral duty to press any of them because it's your
opinion against mine. But my view actually allows there to be universal moral duties saying that it
is a fact we ought to act certain ways. And I think that's a huge deficiency on atheism.
I see what you're saying.
And this is just a point about conflicting kind of base worldview beliefs here.
And I want to move on to talk about something else briefly here.
I hope my point has got across.
But as I say, I'm happy to continue discussing this any time.
I should go to London and have one of those delightful backyard conversations with you
like you do with your friend.
What's his name?
Woodford?
Stephen?
Stephen.
Yeah, that would be good.
Or on the podcast. Sure. One thing I want to ask about is the principle
of sufficient reason. Now, it seems to me that you're quite influenced by Ed Fazer's arguments.
I may be kind of pulling that out of thin air, but from what you said, they seem to have a lot
of correlation. Now, I'm interested if you follow his reasoning in one of the ways that I'm thinking
about here. In the argument from motion or the argument from actualization
of potential, Faser makes the point that whatever actualizes, you know, the thing that actualizes
this mic being here on the stand is the stand, but the stand only holds that actualization
instrumentally because that's actualized by something else. And so it's the actual,
the full explanation for what actualizes the microphone is not the stand because that only has instrumental
Actual actualization via other things in the same way. I would say that the same should in my interpretation
Be true of the principle of sufficient reason that is if a contingent fact is explained by another contingent fact
That contingent fact is also explained by another contingent fact
So the thing that explains whatever contingent fact we're looking at is only instrumentally explanatory, only has instrumental
explanatory power. For it to be a sufficient explanation, as in principle of sufficient reason,
to explain why a contingent thing is the way that it is, you may disagree with my reasoning here,
but let me try and spell this out. We're trying to say that there needs to be a sufficient reason for why something exists,
right?
But if the reason or the explanation for that thing also requires an explanation, then in
the same way as actualization, that explanation is only instrumentally explanatory.
You see what I'm saying?
It's kind of by analogy, it's also only instrumental in its explanation in that that needs to be
explained by something else and that needs to be explained by something else too.
Well, that's the nature of contingent things or the nature of things that are a mixture
of act and potency is that if the thing does not explain itself, it's quite capable of
explaining other things, but we don't have a complete explanation of the state of affairs
because we're stuck at something that still needs explanation.
Sure. So when you say that anything has a sufficient reason, that is a reason that's
all encompassing and explains everything, that to me would imply that you would need to have
all of the instrumental explanations and the base root explanation, be it whatever brute fact you
think it goes back to, which to me makes it seem like the argument for the principle of sufficient reason is begging the question, because to say that something has sufficient reason is essentially to say that you have an explanation which ultimately terminates in a brute fact, that is to assert the existence of the brute fact before you get off the ground.
I don't know if I'm making sense here.
I haven't explained this very well.
know if I'm making sense here. I haven't explained this very well. No, well, I would say that when it comes to explaining things, we can have sufficient explanations. You can have a sufficient explanation
that is not a complete explanation. For example, when I left the house today, I saw there were a
plate of cookies on the table. And so I would think, well, why is there a plate of cookies?
There's a scientific explanation that dough heated in the oven to make a confectionary delight, and a reasonable personal explanation my wife Laura made them.
But I mean, a total one would be like the bread that was harvested, the cocoa that was
made, the oven that was constructed, going all the way back to the Big Bang.
Yeah, but I mean, that seems to be what you would need to actually have a fully sufficient
explanation of why this contingent thing is as it is.
But also, I just want to flag this before we run out of time.
The distinction you've made there, I think, is is a false one you make a distinction between scientific and personal
explanations like boiling the kettle say why do you boil the kettle whether it's the explanation
involving chemistry and the explanation involving um what i want but me wanting a particular type
of drink or something is also scientifically explicable right by like like that that is all
i don't see why that's different just because it involves a person like the the reasons the neurons that are firing in my brain to make me want a particular thing rather than another is just as easily scientifically explainable as the chemistry of the.
a controversial view of the philosophy of mind that even many atheists don't accept, which is that
mental intent, that intentions or mental experiences don't exist. Alex Rosenberg makes this point in his book, The Atheist's Guide to Reality, that an intention would be having
aboutness to something. But in my wife's brain, the neurons, the electrons that are firing,
there's no property of aboutness or chocolate chip cookies, about chocolate chip cookies in there.
So if the only thing that exists are these material objects, we haven't really explained that crucial element of it if you try to reduce mental states and intentions just to a materialist explanation, which even many atheistic philosophers of mind don't do.
They can be property dualists and other things like that. Yeah. Well, I think that looking at my time, I think we've
pretty much run out of time on this section. 40 seconds. Oh, 40 seconds. Okay. Well, I was just
getting ready to pipe down. Do I have any more questions? Abortion. I don't know.
It's quite, I did see someone, I've been glancing over at the live chat, and I remember when I said, you know, I can't talk about or justify abortion one way or the other in four seconds.
And someone was like, yes, you can.
Not in an intelligible, befitting way.
We'll have to save that for another discussion.
For sure.
Yeah.
I'm happy to move on to audience Q&A if that's what comes next. Matt, people are saying they can't hear you.
Oh, I'm sorry.
Sorry, everybody.
Can you hear me now?
All right, we're going to move into 30 minutes of Q&A.
If you direct a question, we'll take one question for Alex,
one question for Trent.
We'll go back and forth like that.
Trent will have two minutes to respond.
And then if he's being asked a question,
then Alex will get to respond to that.
Well, I'm really glad that somebody pointed out
that I was muted because that would not have been fun
to waste the rest of this time.
Okay, so if you have a question,
please put it up in the live chat.
Man, can you believe we have 2,500 people right now?
That's amazing.
I'm pretty sure they can hear me now.
People are still saying you're muted.
Yeah, you know why? They might be a little little I don't know if they're a little delayed
I thought it was a delay but they're still
I don't know someone's saying fixed
I think it's fine now yeah yeah I think it's okay now
what's difficult
is we've got like how many people
2415 people
watching and they're all asking questions at the same time
so let me see if I can
you guys can just take a breather all right let's see i uh question here for
i'm going to throw it up on the screen for alex so alex i'll ask you the question and as soon as
you start answering i'll give you two minutes and i'll cut you off and give trent a minute to
respond can alex explain his perception of how consciousness can be realized with only a
naturalistic phenomenon thanks um well i mean the short answer is no um i think i have just as much
idea about what consciousness is and how it works as anybody else um i i'm not entirely sure i i
know it came up so maybe it is relevant something I said, but I don't see the immediate
relation but like no, I mean
Like to put it bluntly like I don't have a strong opinion on what consciousness is or how it works
But I think that like it's at least plausible that there's a naturalistic explanation for how it
for how it comes about like I mean you can kind of think of
non-conscious perception of surroundings as a very as a very kind of minimal
Trivial version of consciousness that the more complex that becomes that's essentially what consciousness is
But I mean really I I hate to kind of almost refuse the question, but I just don't know
I I don't know what consciousness is. I wouldn't know how to account for it
Okay, I have Trent you have a minute to respond?
Yes, I'm aware of arguments for the existence of God like this, and I'd recommend listeners
to J.P. Moreland's book, The Argument for God from Consciousness. I think the listener brought
it up because I made the point that for an atheist like Alex, he's justified in believing
that he has conscious mental states, even if he cannot give a step-by-step scientific
explanation of how it is the case he has those from a physical brain. Much the same way, I believe
theists and many people are justified in saying they have free will, because free will is just as
seemingly obvious as the fact that I am conscious, even if you can't give a step-by-step physical
explanation, which may be the wrong kind of explanation to give for this sort of phenomena.
That as I said before, if you're morally responsible, which girds the moral realism I defended,
then I think it shows that you have free will, and you can believe in that even if you don't
have a step-by-step explanation for it.
Okay, thanks very much.
Question for Trent.
This is M. Jordan.
He says, how can we have free will in heaven yet not be sinful? Why
didn't God do that from the very beginning? What is his point of testing us if he already knows
the outcome? Go for it. Well, what I would say is that it's not about a test, and so this goes
back to Alex's argument, which is, why didn't God just create a world of only moral agents who only choose the good?
And God could have made a world like that if he had just made human beings immediately in his presence and gave them perfected wills,
so that if they have perfect wills and their intellect never fails to grasp the good, which is God himself, his beatific vision, then they would apprehend that.
But my point is that God is justified in allowing evil if he can bring about greater goods, and that
a world that goes from imperfect to perfect has goods that this direct heaven creation does not.
And so God is justified in making this world that has those kinds of goods,
namely the virtues that are inextricably tied to vice, like compassion, courage, forgiveness,
mercy. These are good things, and God is justified in allowing them to exist.
And so the other argument I gave was that I think it's good for God to create rational creatures and to respect their freedom, to not simply create them into an existence where, like many atheists will say, God just makes us his slaves.
That might be somewhat of an argument if God made us right in his presence and we just bow down and worship him.
But if he gives us the choice whether to follow him or not, and he freely respects the decisions we make,
then that's a respect of human agency and liberty that I think is a good that should be taken into account that goes against that common caricature of God.
Okay, Alex, you have one minute to respond. Yeah, I mean, I understand what you're saying,
but I think that there are some interesting implications, such as the idea that once you
get to heaven, the fact that you're kind of fully apprehending God means that you will always choose
to do the good, because once you're in heaven, you're kind of fully apprehending god means that you will always choose to do the good because once you're in heaven you're kind of you're essentially being
psychologically coerced into doing it this is this is one thing that i i think there are some
interesting implications about the freedom of conscious creatures when the kind of the argument
relies on the idea that in order to be freely good you have to be free you have to have the
capability of being freely evil as well but if you're essentially saying that once you get to
heaven the reason evil doesn't exist is because people just they just can't psychologically bring themselves to commit it because they're in the presence of the good
Then that's the same thing as saying they're not capable of committing evil in which case are they really freely choosing?
To commit the good if you say something like well, they do still freely choose to commit the good
They just I mean they can still commit evil
They just kind of choose not to then I I'd be interested to know whether you think that it's logically possible that there would be an event like the Holocaust in heaven,
because to me, my intuition says that that wouldn't be the case. Maybe you think it is,
but in order to say that actually, no, there is still some kind of free choice going on there,
you could say that they don't in practice choose to commit a Holocaust, but they could if they
wanted to, and I think that's not a a great implication next question from manuel he says
and this is for alex why do you think a perfectly good being god is obligated to maximize the
pleasure or minimize the unnecessary suffering of his creatures in class and then he says theist
goodness in depth of creatures okay so i think you got the gist of the question did you
yeah i mean i if i used that language it was probably just to avoid the complications of goodness in depth of creatures. Okay, so I think you got the gist of the question, did you?
Yeah, I mean, if I used that language,
it was probably just to avoid the complications of trying to use words like good and evil,
which people don't like me using a lot of the time.
The point that I'm trying to make is one on the theistic worldview.
So I think if there is such thing as a maximally,
I'm essentially following JL Mackey here
and saying that if there is a perfectly moral being, it will minimize evil wherever it can.
People don't like the way that I'm using evil. So I say whatever you take to be a criterion of evil, just just slot in the word there.
But perhaps more generally just worded as that, I think that if there is such thing as objective morality, if there is such thing as a God who's perfectly moral, then I think that he would minimize whatever is objectively evil.
then I think that he would minimize whatever is objectively evil. And that's what I'm saying leads to the view that whatever evil exists in the world right now,
if there is a perfectly moral God, exists necessarily, and there couldn't be any more or any less.
Now that's something that Trent disagreed with, and we kind of danced around the subject a little bit.
I don't think we really pinned it down, but I think that's the implication that you're led to.
If you're going to say that there is a perfectly moral being and a perfectly moral being will minimize evil,
that whatever you take to be evil, there necessarily exists exactly the right amount
right now because there couldn't be any more or any less. I hope that makes sense.
All right. Trent. Yeah. And I disagree with Mackie's premise that a perfectly moral being
will minimize evil because you could do that. Like if I'm a perfectly moral being will minimize evil, because you could do that. Like, if I'm a perfectly moral being and I had the antimatter device that could destroy the whole
universe instantaneously, as a perfect being, I should press the button because I'll bring the
amount of evil in the universe down to zero. So I just disagree with that premise in Mackey's
argument. My view is that if God is perfectly moral, then any evil he allows to exist—evil's not a thing he makes, it's an absence of good—any
evil that he allows to exist will be justified, because in doing so, God either makes—he
prevents greater evils, or he brings about greater goods, which, as I said, is a principle that
we justify among humans, and if that's justified among humans, tolerating evil for greater goods.
Like, we build roads to other towns, even though there will be people who die from car accidents.
We allow free speech, even though people will say horrid things.
Then we can apply that to God.
And then I can't help but comment on the last question.
No, there will not be a Holocaust in heaven.
Ever.
Impossible.
Impossible.
Impossible.
Impossible.
Next question is for Trent.
Impossible. Impossible. Impossible.
Next question is for Trent.
What are your thoughts on Adam and Eve only eating plants pre-fall?
Does this not offer support for the idea that Christians should aim to be vegan?
Go for it.
Well, I don't see anything—in the Genesis account, it does talk about how Adam and Eve were given every green plant in the garden to eat.
The Catechism of the Catholic Church says in paragraph 390 that the account of the fall in Genesis—I think it's 390—the account of the fall in Genesis 1 through 3 affirms a primeval event, but it's written in symbolic language.
So, you know, so it's presenting truths, but not necessarily in a literal historical sense. So to derive a universal moral duty from that, I think would be unfounded.
As a Christian, I would say that we have the moral permission to eat animals, but we also have the
moral duty to not cause unnecessary suffering among animals.
Obviously, that would include directly torturing animals,
but I'm extremely sympathetic to Alex's view that much of factory farming causes unnecessary suffering.
And I've actually been criticized by other Catholics for saying this,
that there could come a point where we say that it is immoral to eat food that comes from certain kinds of animal meat production
that involve unnecessary suffering.
But I don't believe that animals have the same moral status as human beings.
OK. Yeah. I mean, I would only have to add that I think I think if people want to put this bluntly,
Jesus would probably have some choice words if you took him on a tour of a modern factory farm.
I would just point out that I agree with you there, Trent, that it's not necessarily intrinsically wrong to kill an animal and eat it or to eat an animal product in any circumstance.
What's wrong is committing unnecessary suffering. In your words, you say like
unnecessary suffering in order to produce that food. I would say that because we now live in a
situation whereby we don't need animal products to survive and because killing an animal in most
cases and certainly the production of things like milk and the separation of calves from their mother do cause suffering by definition that's unnecessary
suffering because we don't need to do it to survive and therefore you should be giving up
milk that's the only thing that i would have to add if you wanted to you say you're sympathetic
to the argument and people like to say yeah i'm with you on the factory farming stuff well if you're
with me on the factory farming stuff then stop funding it all right another conversation indeed
just so you know trent and Alex, I'll cut you off
after the two minutes, so don't feel like you're... I'll let you know if you go over your time.
So this next question is for Alex from David John. He says, have you become more convinced
or more doubting of atheistic principles through talking to the likes of William Land Craig,
et cetera? Thanks. Well, I'd be careful to use words like atheistic principles.
I'm not sure such things exist, but I know that I understand the grammar of the question.
And yes, absolutely. No, no doubt in my mind whatsoever since studying at university.
And it's not so much the actual the course itself, but the people I've met, some of my best friends, most of them are religious.
And we have these amazing conversations. I've had great luck to speak to people like William Lane
Craig, who I have great respect for, and used to be part of the crowd, who would kind of just
chime in and say, oh, these dishonest apologist charlatans, and I can't believe,
it's so obvious that I knew nothing about what I was talking about, and now I,
so, so much more. That's why i said in my opening statement that
the problem of animal suffering is the main thing that's stopping me from uh seriously entertaining
theism uh because if that problem is solved if i can find a solution for that then i could very
easily uh see myself becoming religious if if i found you know a deductive argument that i thought
worked you know if you could break the symmetry of planting as ontological argument i believe in
god like that it's as simple as that like i've become i know, if you could break the symmetry of Plantinga's ontological argument, I believe in God like that. It's as simple as that. Like I've become,
I've come to realize that if the argument is presented and it's, and it's presented and it's
valid and it's sound, like there's just no escape from that. So I think I have certainly more
respect for the arguments that I've been responding to because of conversations with people like
Craig, but also I've, I've, I've realized more've realized more that if an argument was out
there, it could convince me in a heartbeat. Sure. And I would say on this, answering the
question, I guess, from my perspective hearing it, I would agree the problem of animal suffering
is a difficult one for theists to confront, at least at an emotional level. I do think,
though, that once again, these probabilistic arguments that just make God less likely,
they'll always be defeated by a demonstrable argument.
Like, you know, the example I gave is that
if I have ironclad evidence that I'm innocent, like an alibi,
even if there's really damning evidence against me,
like your fingerprints are on the gun,
like, oh yeah, that is hard to explain.
But then if I've got this demonstrable thing to outweigh it,
then the theist still
comes out on top. So I think with the evidential arguments, when we do evidential arguments against
God, it's only fair to also include all the evidence that is for God as well, to see where
the scales tip. But also for me, the distinction about animal suffering is that—
If you're going to wrap up.
For me—oh, am I done?
Yeah, you can wrap up your thought if you want to.
Oh, is that the way to resolve the moral duty we have towards animals without veering into
arbitrary human value and equality, or an unlivable human-non-human equality and ethics,
that one, the difficulty that arises from that pushes me more towards the theistic
moral realism and Christian view on the subject. All right, this next question from Andrew Montpetit
says, science leans on the assumption something has the capacity to be understood. So Trent,
how do the limits of humanity's capacity play into your understanding of seemingly random events?
And then I look forward to hearing Alex's
response. Well, yeah. So Alex brought up the idea that there are events that are random that might
not have a reason for why they occur, but I don't believe that that cuts against the idea that
there's a principle of sufficient reason to explain why things exist. So a famous example of
this is a farmer plowing his field and he comes
across buried treasure by chance. Like it would seem random that he was just plowing in that
place. And why did he, why did he get the treasure in that place? It doesn't show there's no
principle of sufficient reason because there is a reason why the treasure exists and why the farmer
is plowing. Chance and randomness only make sense
as being the byproducts of natural predictable laws of nature and reality. So if a rock falls
down a hill and crushes a smaller rock by chance, quote unquote, that's only because there are
predictable laws and explanations for why rocks exist, why certain forces move them in the way
they do, why their potential is
actualized. And it's within that framework of predictability and sufficient reasons that we
get these random events. That's why going back when Alex was talking about these experiments
that are performed, I really do think that makes the case I'm talking about. Because if you didn't
have PSR, one, you couldn't uniformly do these experiments and get the same result every single time.
And without PSR, you'd have a lot of reason to doubt whether your own sensory experiences of these events was trustworthy,
because you wouldn't know that it's actually happening with kind of a reliable predictability.
For more on that, I would recommend Alex Pruss' book on the principle of sufficient reason,
that Pruss and Kuhn go into that in more detail.
Okay, Alex feel free to respond and take an extra 30 seconds if you like since Trent took a little longer on that last one.
Sorry, I would second the book recommendation and I would also say that, Trent,
I think you've just kind of defined randomness out of existence there.
Like the whole point is that yeah, if a farmer randomly kind of digs up some treasure that that's not actually random
That's that's like the whole argument is that well
There is an explanation for why that was there you you can if you knew all the kind of facts about the universe if you knew
Kind of you know who buried it there why the farmer went this way instead of that way what was going on in his brain
Which way the wind was blowing you know how hot how how?
Sharp that the tool was that he was digging with so how how deep it would go, all these kind of things,
then you could predict and explain,
yeah, that's why he hit the treasure,
so it's not actually random, right?
The point is that, generally speaking,
most scientists, from the time of Newton at least, thought that the universe acted in accordance
with these deterministic laws,
even if there were certain things like, you know,
somebody randomly coming across something,
quote-unquote, as you say, and I think the reason you say quote unquote is because you realize it's
not true randomness. People thought, well, even if we can't explain it because there are too many
variables, there is an explanation. If you flip a coin, it's almost impossible to know all the
variables to predict exactly which way it would flip. But if you knew all the variables, you
could predict with 100 percent accuracy which way it flip. That is, the only thing that would be
truly random is something like which we observe
in quantum mechanics. And
if that does hold, which it does,
then we have what we would call true randomness,
which means not just something that appears to happen
randomly but does actually have an explanation,
but something that actually occurs and exists
with no explanation. Okay. Excellent.
Thank you. This next question,
we have a super chat. Thank you so much.
This is Irving Nester.
He says, this is for Alex. Quantum randomness only implies a limitation of knowledge of an outcome.
Why can't God ordain this limitation and quantum laws and thus be the explanation while not having
the limitation himself? Sorry, can you repeat it one more time? Yeah, you got it.
Quantum randomness only implies
a limitation of knowledge of an outcome.
Why can't God ordain this limitation
and quantum laws and thus be the explanation
while not having the limitation himself?
Yeah, well, look, I might be misinterpreting
what you're saying, but you seem to say
that quantum mechanics implies that we just kind of don't know which way something's gonna go like
The principle is not that the principle is that we can't know because nothing determines it right that is what the experiment in 2015
Finally proved and by the way, they've been doing experiments. It's like the 80s
But they finally actually conclusively proved it without loopholes in 2015. It's not just kind of like ah, yeah
Well, you know, there's there's no way for us to know there's kind of like uh yeah well you know there's there's
no way for us to know there's some hidden variable that we can't see there's there's something
preordained about it that we just can't access what it proves is that like it cannot be preordained
in that in that sense even in a naturalistic sense it can't be from the point at which the
photons are released um you could not know even in principle and that means even if you're the divine creator of
the universe um unless i suppose you could think of it in terms of seeing the future but it would
be in the future there'd be nothing that you could see at that instance even if you knew all true
facts about the universe that would tell you what was going to happen or which way uh that particular
photon was going to spin that's the point it's not like a practical limitation it's a it's a
limitation in principle um so i think the kind think the question maybe kind of misunderstands the point that I was making
in the first place. Okay, Trent. Yeah, I think we've talked past each other a little bit about
PSR, but the limited principle of sufficient reason that I argued for was just that things
which exist have a reason for why they exist. You don't just come across things that exist for no reason whatsoever.
So when we talk, for example, of quantum mechanics, like the reason a beta particle, a decaying beta particle from an atomic nucleus exists is because it was brought about by the atomic decay in that nucleus.
So the atomic nucleus is the explanation for why the beta particle exists.
Now, Alex, I say we'll go deeper. Why does it exist at that time rather than another time?
And we would attribute that to the property of an atomic nucleus generating beta particles
according to some kind of probabilistic framework. So it's a, there's not like there's just
no causes or determinate causes.
There can be causes that are indeterminate.
And so God can even know those by various reasons.
The Thomistic view would be that since he upholds everything in existence, he knows everything that will happen, including these probabilistic causes.
The next question, which is directed at Trent.
Thank you, Gina, for being one of the super chats here.
She says, Trent, have you read Christopher Steck on a Catholic framework for animal theology? And
if so, what do you think of it? For your information, Alex, I recommended Trent Doherty
to start with on the problem of animal suffering. Go for it, Trent.
No, sorry, I have no thoughts on that so many books to read uh and then and there
are uh different views trent doherty is one um uh was a gentleman who wrote nature read
tooth and claw michael murray i think is his name um has another explanation on that point
uh but i have not read that particular work, though I do think
that, once again, the baseline here when it comes to the evidential argument from evil, we must not
forget, is that if the demonstrative arguments for God's existence work, then no probabilistic
argument from evil can overcome them. I would appeal to my courtroom analogy, the trial analogy
that I made earlier. If it's just probabilistic, it can't beat demonstrative. Much the same way, if an atheist had 100% logical proof
God did not exist, no evidential argument for God could beat that either. So when we're doing
these evidential arguments, all of it has to be on the table, otherwise it's not a fair assessment
of evidence. You can't look just at one piece of evidence at trial. You've got to look at all the evidence. When it comes with God, the evidential
argument against evil, all of it has to be on the table to be weighed. Okay. Go for Alex.
I would just say, well, thank you for the recommendation of Trent's book. I spoke to
Trent yesterday, and we'll definitely be discussing the book with him at some point.
And I think, yeah, it's a good place to start.
I agree with you.
I'm not sure exactly if I have anything to say on the point.
I can't remember what the original question actually was.
Who's this reading?
If I had read a book.
Yeah, yeah.
It's just a book recommendation.
Yeah, I'm not sure I really have anything to add in that case.
No worries.
Although I would perhaps just say that I think I agree with you, Trent, that evidential arguments don't hold the same weight as deductive arguments do.
I would say that there is a logical form of the problem of evil that could be pulled out of what we're discussing.
For instance, if you do accept that a maximally good being would minimize evil, then I think there is a logical point that can be made there.
But if you reject that, then I would agree with you that, yeah. Back to what was said earlier about, you
know, if I'm more sympathetic to these arguments, it's like, if you can produce a deductive argument
that God exists and that God is perfectly moral and it was valid and sound, then the problem of
evil would kind of just dissipate. It would become a problem of explaining it, not trying to kind of
discuss whether it means God exists or not. Right.
Next question here comes from Andrew Connor, and this is for alex alex have you studied soren kirkegaard and could knowledge
beyond human discovery exist and again if you haven't read that specifically feel free just
to talk about the general topic i have a a little bit um uh and we studied uh fear and trembling in depth um wait no uh look i i i have not sorry i think
i'm getting mixed up there no yeah that's right that's correct yeah yeah uh yeah uh what was the
but what was the second part of the question um let me see here uh have you studied uh could
knowledge beyond human discovery that's right exist um i think could knowledge beyond human discovery exist?
I think that knowledge beyond human discovery, I think not.
The reason being because although there's not a fully agreed upon analysis of what knowledge is, I think one of the things that knowledge does require, one of the necessary conditions of knowledge, is that you believe it's the case. And so if it's kind of beyond
human comprehension or beyond human access, then I don't think it could count as knowledge.
Unless, I suppose, you could posit something like a divine intellect, in which case knowledge can
exist in the divine intellect but isn't accessible to human beings, maybe. But if you tried to use
that to prove God's say, that would be begging the question, I think. I think that if you're
talking about human knowledge, there can't be such thing.
But I suppose maybe you're trying to kind of talk about
there being such thing as divine knowledge,
in which case, sure, if God existed, yeah,
there could be knowledge that's inaccessible to human beings.
And if that's maybe an implication,
if that's maybe supposed to have an implication
for the problem of evil,
like, you know, there's some explanation
or there's something that God knows that we can't,
then sure, fine.
It just wouldn't do much for the debates that that we have as human beings in our human capacity. Okay, Trent
Yeah, I don't know how Kierkegaard would would fit into this he was a 19th century Christian existentialist
Who has interesting writings though? I would prefer the writings of Blaise Pascal to him when When it comes to knowledge beyond human discovery, I would say absolutely, because I would say there
are infinite amounts of knowledge. We have infinite sets, for example, in mathematics.
Knowledge of the universe beyond human comprehension, if knowledge is justified true belief.
We have many beliefs, like I could believe there are an odd number of atoms in the universe.
I don't know how we're ever going to know whether that's true or false.
I don't think human beings could ever reach technological capacity to answer the question.
But it's definitely true or it's definitely false.
But I do think that alludes back to an argument I made earlier,
which is that if these truths, some of them are necessary,
like mathematical truths, propositional truths,
if they are necessary and they exist,
then they must exist in some kind of necessarily existing mind.
And that provides more evidence for the kind of the divine intellect that Alex referenced.
Okay, thank you.
Yeah, so I may have misunderstood.
I think if you mean the truth exists that we couldn't know, then yeah, absolutely.
Sure.
All right, here's the final question.
I think this is a great question to end on.
And I'll give you both two minutes if you'd like to answer this.
This comes from one of our patrons, Vincent Wise.
He says, I would love to hear each of them comment on the argument they struggle the hardest to answer.
It's always interesting to learn how a person deals with their weaker points.
So I guess the question here is, I could ask Alex,
what do you think is the most formidable argument for theism?
And then I'll ask Trent, what's the most formidable argument for atheism?
So Alex, go for it.
It's a difficult question to answer because it's like
it's impossible to tell what effect an argument is having on me until it actually finally works.
I don't kind of feel slightly pulled and then fully pulled. It's like it either gets me or it
doesn't. As I briefly mentioned a moment ago, I think ontological arguments are some of my
favorite. I prefer rationalistic thinking to kind of empirical argumentation or something so like I'm
fascinated by ontological arguments for the existence of God and I love the idea of being able to kind of
Talk about the existence of a necessary being through thought alone
I think that that's where the potential lies to make me believe in a necessary being or something like that
I do think perhaps maybe there's some interesting arguments about consciousness. My friend Jonathan McClatchy raised a point to me recently that evil
is an argument in favor of God and not for the kind of reasons that someone like yourself would
put forward. But he said essentially in a Bayesian sense, he was like, well, evil presupposes
consciousness. And because consciousness is so much more likely on theism than atheism, evil is
actually kind of by a kind of long way around,
it's actually argument in favor of God.
And I thought that was really fascinating and interesting.
I think the mystery of consciousness has a lot to be unpacked
and has plenty of potential.
But I'm afraid I just don't really know until it convinces me.
But I think the most potential lies in ontological arguments.
Okay.
Trent, what's the most formidable argument for atheism
that you find most difficult to answer?
Well, I think it's gonna be the argument from evil
It does pose
Intellectual problems to overcome. I do not believe they're insurmountable
But I do think that as human beings we're not computers. We're not Vulcans. We don't rationally process everything
You know if you if you fit, you, when Alex was talking about arguments moving him, he almost talked about, like, saying,
when did you know that you loved so-and-so?
It's like, well, it's hard to tell. There's no step-by-step process. It just kind of hit me.
And I think it's something similar with, you know, these arguments or coming to know people.
So I think that evil, it impacts us in that non-rational way that many people come to
believe in God for rational reasons and also non-rational reasons. Not irrational, but non-rational.
That just the same, you can assert the worthiness of having a personal relationship with someone
because of the beauty that they exude, and for other non-rational reasons, I think that that
works for God. So then, of course, the ugliness in the world could make you quite angry with God,
and understandably so, and sometimes I get angry.
I'm like, God, why is this happening?
And I'm comforted that in the New Testament, in 1 Peter 5,
it says to cast all your anxieties on him for he cares for you.
So sometimes, yeah, the horrid evils I see just make me want to throw my hands up.
But if I threw God out of the picture, all I'd be left with is the horrid evils.
It would still be horrible and miserable and awful, but there'd be no possibility for any kind of vindication or compensation.
So for me, I don't see the need to do that with God unless someone shows me there's evidence beyond that that he's either incoherent or that all the
arguments simply don't work. But I'm sympathetic to how the argument can pull people, but I believe
there are strong ways out of it. Okay. Well, thank you very much, guys. That was really fascinating.
We're going to take five minutes each for closing statements, and we're going to begin with you,
Trent, when you're ready, and then we'll move on to Alex. So just let me know.
we're going to begin with you, Trent, when you're ready, and then we'll move on to Alex. So just let me know. Well, we covered a lot of ground here in this debate. And what's hard with these debates,
I mean, any limited time format, unless we were Bertrand Russell and Father Copleston, and we just
talked for hours and hours and hours on hand, and maybe there'll be a time for that. But I think,
given the time constraints people have, I think there'll be a time for that. But I think, given the time constraints
people have, I think debates like this serve an important purpose. They may convince some people
God exists, they may convince some people that he doesn't exist. You might watch and be unmoved in
your feeling about it. At the end of the day, though, I hope that debates like these will
encourage you to really own your belief on the matter, whether your belief is that God exists or your
belief—even atheists have a positive belief, like no arguments prove God exists. I would just say,
whoever you are watching this, own that belief. We referenced many things tonight. Go and read up on
that more. Visit our YouTube channels, Alex's and mine, and read the articles we've written
to go deeper in that. And so I would just say that, look, for those who are considering atheism or rejecting God, I would say you can do
that, but you pay a high price in choosing atheism. You do, because in rejecting the
arguments that were proposed tonight, as we saw with Alex in our engagement, an atheist, I believe,
has to be prepared to reject many truths about reality
that seem quite sensible.
Truths about causality, truths about the principle of sufficient reason, that things that exist
have explanations.
I think that through the course of this debate, there was not a fatal objection lodged against
my arguments from causal finitism, the arguments for a purely actual actualizer, even for the
arguments for a necessary being, or one that is the full ground of morality.
So when you look at morality, I think especially if you follow the morality Alex puts forward in
his particular atheistic worldview, you have to embrace many controversial positions, as we saw
in tonight's debate, about whether is it true that it's always wrong to do some things like
murder an innocent person
or to rape someone? Is morality objective? I think if you saw tonight's debate, if you embrace
Alex's particular atheistic view, it leads to some heavily morally counterintuitive positions.
And if you don't want to embrace those, I would say embrace a theistic view of the world,
of God being perfect goodness itself, who created us in his image.
And so regardless of where you move forward, remember that you are made in God's image, you are loved. The only reason you exist is because God wanted you to exist, and you are
valuable. So as you go and talk and discuss, and maybe go in the comments section below this video,
try to remember you and the person you talk to are valuable. Even if you don't believe it,
you're valuable because you're made in God's image. You have an everlasting life and unique,
uncountable worth. And so if God does exist, and I think my arguments have shown that,
then it makes it more likely that maybe God interacted in the world, such as by supernaturally
performing a miracle, like raising a man from the dead, a topic we unfortunately could not explore in tonight's debate, but maybe we'll explore in a
future debate or discussion. And I hope you will explore those questions as well. And I'm grateful
for all of you who watched the whole debate. And I just encourage you, once again, pursue the truth,
no matter the cost. I will yield my time
Thanks I don't have too much to say either I would potentially second the essence if not
the practicalities of everything Trent just said I would I would agree on the the the key point I
think is that one of the best ways to investigate beliefs that we hold is to investigate what they lead to and other incompatibilities that they might hold with other intuitions or beliefs that we hold.
You might not realize that a particular belief about the problem of evil might lead you to think that something that you don't think should be morally permitted is morally permitted. And you might have to explore that as Trent's tried to show. But I
also think, you know, it can it can happen the other way, too. I think that if you hold something
like the principle of sufficient reason, you might find that you're in for a bit of trouble
when it comes to understanding the implications that quantum mechanics has for that and realizing
that you're throwing out a lot of other scientific principles, too, which I wish we'd have had a bit
more time to speak about, because I'd love to show exactly how,
by holding on to the principle of sufficient reason, you essentially kind of throw out our
traditional understanding of causation, which I think undermines a lot of what religious people
like to use to justify their conception of God. I would say just beware that these kind of things
exist and explore them fruitfully, because it's all very well and good being able
to defend each in isolation but if they're incompatible with each other then something is
wrong but also remember after all like even if you kind of look at these inconsistencies and you and
you and you adapt your world to you accordingly and everything's kind of existing consistently
you can be consistently wrong so there's kind of another stage of the process there you know make
sure that everything you believe consistency is kind of the first step to take to make sure that something is coherent,
but then kind of test it in the second stage of analysis to find out if it's actually true.
But yeah, even though I'm not going to justify it in the same way Trent did, I would also
generally kind of agree with the proposition, be nice to each other in the comments.
Remember that that other person is an animal with maybe not intrinsic worth, but some kind of
vague extrinsic worth related to their capacity for pleasures and pains. So, you know, be nice.
But yeah, I think, you know, because of the amount of stuff that we had to say,
there doesn't seem like a kind of very good conclusive sentiment that I could kind of put
here because there are so many kind of avenues that are left open. But I think it would be
interesting to perhaps have that longer form conversation with you trying to some point,
maybe on a podcast or something. I'm not quite sure when, but I feel like, you know,
debate format is good for opening questions, but it's not always great for answering them fully.
So maybe we should try and do that at another point. But I just I would just thank you both
and thank everyone for listening. Sure. I would enjoy that, and I'm grateful you were here. It's
a very fruitful exchange and one that I think should be ended with the sign to be continued.
Very good. Very good. Well, I've put both Trent's YouTube channel and Alex's YouTube channel
directly below in the description of this video, so the show notes, so please be sure to click that.
But why don't we just wrap up real quick? You guys did fantastic. Thank you so much for being below in the description of this video. So the show notes, so please be sure to click that.
But why don't we just wrap up real quick. You guys did fantastic. Thank you so much for being so charitable and awesome. So maybe just as we wrap up here, each of you tell our listeners
and viewers where they can learn more about you. Alex. Sure. Well, I'll start. You can, yeah,
you can, affirmative. I'll just start. I'll let Alex close. I would say
you can go to Catholic.com
much of my work is there
my podcast, The Council of Trent, C-O-U-N-S-E-L
is available on iTunes and Google Play
so Council of Trent, and you can support
the work that I do. The Council of Trent is also
the YouTube channel, so you can go Council of Trent YouTube
and if you want to support what I'm doing
feel free to check out trenthornpodcast.com
to support everything that's happening there.
Alex?
I'm pretty much everything forward slash Cosmic Skeptic because it's such an unusual name.
And my podcast has a much less interesting and genius name, which is just the Cosmic Skeptic Podcast.
Unfortunately, I still can't get over how great of a name that was for yours.
Yeah, you can find me pretty
much anywhere online forward slash cosmic skeptic except tiktok where uh someone took the name
cosmic skeptic and you know it's not like i'm doing dances on there or anything i'm having
discussions about animal ethics so if that's your kind of thing then then you can go on there uh you
can find me at ask a vegan um because i don't know if I mentioned that I'm vegan yet in this debate, but
in case you're interested, I am, and it's something I like
to talk about, and I do that on there.
But yeah, everywhere else is Cosmic Skeptic.
Very good. Well, thank you so much, guys.
I just want to make three announcements before we wrap
up today. The first
is the very next debate that we're going to
be having on this channel. I'll throw it up
on the screen so you can see it. It's going to be a debate
between Father Gregory Pine and Ben Watkins from Real Atheology, and that will be happening on
September 1st, 8 p.m. Eastern Standard Time. So please be sure to subscribe. Click that bell
button. It supports the channel, and you'll obviously be notified when that comes about. And then two more announcements that I want to make here is that, here we go, in October of this
year, the 23rd through the 25th, I'm going to be hosting the largest Catholic apologetics conference
that's ever happened. We are getting a hundred brilliant speakers and, well, I don't know if
they're all brilliant, but they're all pretty bloody articulate and faithful
to the church and very good presenters and we're
hoping to get around 60,000
people. What's great about
this conference is that
it's 100% free and
you can obviously attend no matter where
you are. So I will
put a link in the description as soon as I'm
done. Feel free to put your name, email address
and we'll let you know as soon as the registration page shows up.
And then finally, I just want to say thank you to all of my patrons
who make these shows possible.
What I'm trying to do as we progress here is actually, like today's episode,
just pay a stipend to our debaters
because they obviously have to put a lot of work into this,
and I thank them for it.
So if you want to become a patron at patreon.com slash mattfradd,
you get a bunch of
free things in return like beer steins and signed books and stickers and all that jazz
so thank you very much uh thank you uh to trent and alex uh again and uh see you later thank you