The Daily Stoic - Professor Martha Nussbaum On Humanity's Obligation To Protect Animal Rights
Episode Date: July 19, 2023Ryan speaks with Martha Nussbaum about her new book Justice for Animals: Our Collective Responsibility, the problems that can arise with the Stoic focus on the internal over the external, how... the loss of her daughter taught her what to dedicate the rest of her life to, why animals should be considered citizens of a society, the actions that Martha is personally taking to protect animal rights, and more.Martha Nussbaum is an American philosopher, author, animal rights activist, and the current Ernst Freund Distinguished Service Professor of Law and Ethics at the University of Chicago, where she is jointly appointed in the law school and the philosophy department. She received her BA from NYU and her MA and PhD from Harvard, and she has taught at Harvard, Brown, and Oxford Universities and is currently the Ernst Freund Distinguished Service Professor of Law and Ethics, appointed in the Department of Philosophy and the Law School. Her work, which has garnered 24 major awards since 1990, focuses on Ancient Greek and Roman philosophy, feminist philosophy, political philosophy, and philosophy and the arts. Her seminal books include Anger, Mercy, Revenge (The Complete Works of Lucius Annaeus Seneca), The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy, Cultivating Humanity: A Classical Defense of Reform in Liberal Education, and From Disgust to Humanity: Sexual Orientation and Constitutional Law (Inalienable Rights). Since her daughter’s tragic death in 2019, Martha has dedicated her time to picking up the animal rights work that her daughter was passionate about.✉️ Sign up for the Daily Stoic email: https://dailystoic.com/dailyemail🏛 Check out the Daily Stoic Store for Stoic inspired products, signed books, and more.📱 Follow us: Instagram, Twitter, YouTube, TikTok, FacebookSee Privacy Policy at https://art19.com/privacy and California Privacy Notice at https://art19.com/privacy#do-not-sell-my-info.
Transcript
Discussion (0)
Welcome to the Daily Stoic Podcast where each weekday we bring you a meditation inspired
by the ancient Stoics, a short passage of ancient wisdom designed to help you find strength
and insight here in everyday life.
And on Wednesdays, we talk to some of our fellow students of ancient philosophy,
well-known and obscure, fascinating and powerful. With them, we discuss the strategies and habits
that have helped them become who they are, and also to find peace and wisdom in their actual lives.
But first, we've got a quick message from one of our sponsors.
Hey, it's Ryan Holiday. Welcome to another episode of the Daily Stoic Podcast. I don't want to leave anyone out here.
So if I do, please forget me.
But there are a few living luminaries in the field of stoicism today. Translators, scholars on
stoicism. Greg Rehaze, who obviously I've raved about many times, is one of them. Brad Sellers is one,
Massimo Pignolucci is one. Donald Robertson is one, although not necessarily
an academic, Shady Barch, who we've had on the podcast is certainly one. And then there is
Martha Nussbaum, who is not just a leading scholar on stoicism, but one of the leading philosophers
of our time, one of the best known philosophers,
she pops up in the New York Times, she gave the Jefferson Lecture for the National Endowment
of the Humanities in 2016.
In 2016, she won the Kyoto Prize in Arts and Philosophy, she won the Bergruin Prize in Philosophy and Culture.
In 2020, she won the Holburg Prize, 2022 she were in the balls in prize.
She happens to be a distinguished service professor of law and ethics at the University of Chicago,
where she is one of the few professors jointly appointed in the law school and the philosophy department. And she just has a wide range of philosophical interests, ancient Greek and Roman
philosophy, political philosophy, existentialism, feminism, ethics, and more recently,
as we talk about in today's podcast, Animal Rights.
She is picking up the baton of her daughter
who was an animal rights activist
and passed tragically young.
So when we talked about stoicism for today's episode,
we weren't just talking about this sort of dry abstract thing,
this academic thing, but again, something that Martha herself was having to lean on as Cicero did, as Marcus
Arrellius did, as many of the Stokes did, and people in the ancient world did when they were
overwhelmed by grief and loss and tragedy and pain, right? And I would say also, as they did now, and we do now,
as they struggled to make an imperfect world a bit more just, right? And that is the subject
of Martha's new book, Justice for Animals, our collective responsibility, which came out in January.
She's written a book called Not for Profit, why democracy needs the humanities, the monarchy of fear,
upheavals of thought, and she is also a prolific translator of the Stoics. She is one of the
translators of a very interesting work on Seneca called Anger, Mercy, and Revenge, the complete works of Seneca,
which I quite enjoyed, and we talked about in today's episode. Anyways, an absolute fascinating
thinker, writer, philosopher, and human being, who I was very happy to talk to in today's episode,
and I think you are going to get a lot out of. So thank you to Martha for all of her work.
Thank you for her inspiring example.
And thanks for coming on the podcast. leading hotel brands Hilton and Marriott. Stair down family drama and financial disasters.
Listen to business wars on Amazon music
or wherever you get your podcasts.
Well, it's lovely to talk with you.
I am a big fan and I think this is my first one from you,
your translation of
Comconification.
Oh, okay. I didn't recognize the cover because I think the first edition was a different color, but anyway, I'm glad you like that.
So tell me what areas we're going to cover. Are we going to focus on the new book?
Yes, yes, I have it here. I read it. I thought it was quite good.
I have a bunch of questions for you on that. And I want to talk about the Stokes in general. But let's start with that.
So I've always been curious. Do you think part of the reason, and you talk about this in the book,
that there was this sort of supremacy, especially amongst the Stokes, that humans are special,
of supremacy, especially amongst the Stokes, that humans are special, animals are broots, and this somehow justifies our indifference to their suffering or their feelings or the
things that we inflict on them. How much do you think the indifference to the suffering
of other species was part and parcel of just life being so profoundly full of suffering then that they weren't
capable or didn't have the capacity to care for others.
Well, I think not at all.
I think the stoics are unique in this respect.
I mean, Aristotle thinks a lot about animal capacities, and I'm just writing a new paper
on Aristotle.
Although, we don't know what he thought about animal ethics,
nothing of that survives.
He has a very high opinion of animal intelligence.
He thinks animals have reasoning, have emotions,
have traits of character.
And the Greeks, the Greeks, anyway, didn't read Aristotle.
So that's the first problem.
They were heirs to Plato, and Plato didn't say much about animals, but then the Epicureans also had a very high opinion of animals.
So did the skeptics. So it really is just them. And the question is why them? I actually think a lot
of it is simply ignorance. I mean, they say things about animals that are just ridiculous when you
know anything about animals. And their opponents, like Plutarch, for example, who was a kind of a platenist who was very
pro-animals and pro-animal rights, he said, you know, you can see just if you observe
a dog, that, okay, a dog comes to a fork in the road, there are three paths, it sniffs
down the first path, nothing there, It sniffs down the second path.
And without stopping to pause, it just darts down the third.
And he said, that's really the disjunctive
syllogist.
And the dog has nastered that.
So he was a big defender of animal intelligence.
And then, of course, later, Porphyry wrote
the greatest treatise on animal intelligence
and animal rights in the ancient world.
So butchered Syrabjian, his book Animal Minds in Human Morals, said it was the Stoics alone
and I agree with him, who set the history of philosophy in a bad direction.
And although of course the Christianity and Judaism contributed to that later on, the
Stoics had a very powerful influence on Christian ethics,
and they had a huge, huge influence
on early modern philosophy.
Descartes, Leidenitz, Phenosa, Adam Smith,
they all were mainly indebted to the Stoics.
So I think they were really in a way villains
in this history.
Yeah, I don't know.
When I read meditations and when I've read Seneca, I did sense, for instance, a kind of
weariness and an aversion to the gratuitous violence in the gladiatorial games.
So there was, I think, an aversion in them to needless suffering, but there didn't seem to be much past. It was almost like it was in bad taste to them as opposed to a
violation of the virtue of justice.
Well, I think that's a very good point, and but I do think that they're very opposed to human anger and
aggressiveness. That they are, and they think it achieves no useful purpose purpose and that it betrays the fact that you're too concerned with external goods that you don't control.
So it's true that the stoic sage would be gentle and would probably not inflict a lot
of needless suffering out of anger and violence, but not because of respect for those creatures.
There's full respect for human creatures, but not for any other species.
Yeah, and the reason I ask about
just this sort of general weirdness about suffering
is that there are some passages in meditations
where you get the sense that the war and the violence
that Marcus really sees in his life sort of desensitizes him.
He talks about seeing a severed arm and a foot
and talks about capturing barbarians,
basically like flies.
I just wondered if this otherwise very sensitive
and kind man, maybe at the individual level,
just sees so much of the
Awfulness of Roman life that it it it it prevents him from say
Thinking about what it's like to be a cow or a dog or some other animal
Well, don't forget that he was leading the army in the
Walls is sure sure So it wasn't like he backed off from the suffering
He just thought if you're in the middle of it, you have to distance yourself, or you won't
be able to stand it.
But he persecuted the Christians and he persecuted the Jews, and he carried on this war.
Most of meditation was written on campaign in Parthia.
So I wouldn't give him such a free pass as you would.
I do think it's true that if you're in the middle of a lot of craziness,
the Stoics thought you could bear it.
If you retreat to the inner citadel,
the nice word that Pierre Adot uses for his book on the meditations.
But yeah, but that doesn't mean you're good to other people and things.
Yeah, no, that's true.
I don't see him as seeking outset wars
the way a Caesar or an Alexander the Great would.
And maybe this is a distinction without a difference in your view.
But I just, I see him as someone,
but there's a reading for me of meditations
where this is a guy who's just somewhat disgusted
with how awful human beings can be to each other and maybe no longer believes that he has
much agency to do anything about it, which I'm not excusing him for.
I'm just trying to get where he comes from.
In the same way that a person might look out at our world today and see a war in Europe, see sweatshops,
and concentration camps in China, see factory farming, and just go, it is what it is, what
am I supposed to do about it?
Well, okay. He probably did believe that the universe in some way was just, and it was
directed by Zeus for some good end. But he didn't try to direct
himself toward the best ends. I mean if you think of other Roman emperors Titus
was well known for going out of his way to be merciful to his opponents and to
giving them a break. The lovely Mozart opera La Clamenza di Tito is all about
that and about how even someone who tried to assassinate him gets mercy, but Marcus was not like that.
And of course, the movie gladiator makes him look a little bit better because he in the movie,
he chooses some non-related person who's, you know, what is it, Russell Crowe, who's a very fine
person, but he actually chose comedists to be his successor, who was his son,
and who was the one with the most terrible psychopath and bloodthirsty and so forth.
So I don't know. I think he says that he grew up as a card carrying stoic. He said his first lesson
from his tutor was not to be a fan of the greens or blues at the races or the light
armed or heavy armed gladiators at the circus. And that means you don't care which side wins.
Now that of course means you probably, if you were the commander and that was your role in life,
was to lead this war, you lead it without really caring whether you win, but you lead it quite
vigorously and you don't care about mercy or compassion.
And of course the things that usually people do when they're compassionate, like trying to feed the
hungry and heal the sick, that doesn't matter to a stow it because all those things are a part of
Zeus's plan and tragedies that depict people. Of course, think about the so-and-view of tragedy. So all
these tragic heroes who say, oh, oh, I'm suffering, I've lost my relatives, my family, my
country, they think these tragic heroes are fools. Tragedy is defined by every teedous
as what happens when chance events before all fools. And so they're really rewritten by epictetus so that eapy is supposed to say, oh,
I don't care about my crown or my diet and I don't care about anything. And I only care
about Zeus' plan. But you know, that's a recipe for not caring when people suffer, when
your own people are oppressed, when people are hungry, when your family is suffering.
So I think this Stoics made many great contributions
to philosophy.
And as you know, my own view of what emotions are
is largely based on the Stoic view,
but not the normative view of what emotions we ought to have,
what we ought to care about.
Because of course, they explicitly say
you should not have compassion
any more than you should have anger for you.
Well, I see this most vividly in in Rousticus, Marcus really is philosophy teacher who, you know,
Marcus gets a plum job as basically the governor of the mayor of Rome. And this guy Justin comes across his desk for supposedly being, you
know, speaking against the gods. And you have such cruel sentence being handed down without
even the slightest bit of mercy. I think Santa Cosset on Clemencey is so beautiful and then I contrast that with how some of the
later Stoics operated when they were in the position to be merciful. And I see that as, yeah,
where the rubber meeting the road and not in a good way. Yeah, that's good. But I'm not going to
give Dave Clemente a total pass either because he tells in your own he should not have compassion. No,
miseracordia. But only mercy because that's the virtue of the powerful,
you know, it's the origin of the merchant of Venice, the quality of mercy,
drop of et cetera, like the gentle rain from heaven upon the place beneath.
So it's a virtue of monarchs who just show their immense power by showing mercy,
but it's not real compassion. And I think, I mean, my own favorite in the Roman world is
actually Cicero, because he tries to be a balanced person, but he cares about what actually happens,
and he cares about the Republic, and he cares, well, of course, he cares deeply about his
daughter, but he says the two things he cares about most in the world, his Republic, and he cares deeply about his daughter, but he says the two things
he cares about most in the world, his daughter, and the Roman Republic both died in that same
year, and he lost his life trying to save the Republic in this last-ditch effort.
I think people ought to care about what happens, and they ought to get involved.
And of course, that's what the Stoics explicitly want you not to do. They have various ways of papering that over. And so in Lucansvar, Saly, Akato
is an admirable hero, leading his army through the desert, et cetera. But is that a consistent
picture of what a Stoic would do? I don't know. I don't really think so. And of course,
there are many other depictions of the Stoic hero that are
a little bit fishy in trying to make them compatible with Roman norms. But to me, you know,
Cicero reads the Stoics, he thinks about them, he really frames a lot of his ideas in terms of Stoic
values, Tuskeleton disputations, he's largely agreeing with the Stoics about limiting and getting rid of anger and grief.
But when the rubber meets the road, as you put it, then he mourns for his daughter in
an outsize way that Atticus criticizes, tells him people are mocking you and they're
saying you should come back to the city, but he cares.
And he cares, of course, about the Republic.
And he actually stuck his head out of the litter
and got the axe.
So that was this real.
It's so fascinating, right?
Because writing about these things is one thing
and then you have to be a human being in the world.
I can't imagine Marcus does not grieve
the half dozen children that he has to bury.
I don't care how much stoic philosophy you've studied.
It's going to rip your heart out.
I don't know how.
I don't know how he got out of bed in the morning.
I sometimes think about that.
How does this guy keep going?
You think about the blow after blow that life deals this guy.
Two decades of peace under Antoninus,
and then he takes over and one thing after another happens,
professionally, and then personally,
is his wife unfaithful,
he's burying child after child,
common is his deeply problematic.
And you know, he not only gets out of bed every morning,
he's writing in meditations about how he has to basically do it with a smile
and a sense of purpose and eagerness. It is remarkable in that sense.
Well, I think the children I wouldn't agree with you so much,
because I think first of all, men in that era didn't have much to do with their children.
They were barely aware of them.
But the death of children was so common that I think no one really attached themselves
to the child until the child was maybe six months or a year old at least.
And so I think we've changed and we do think every newborn child is very precious.
But I don't think anyone in the Greek and Roman world actually thought that just because
the child infant mortality.
I don't know.
I don't know.
There's a couple letters between him and Fronto where they're both talking about grief
and loss, particularly about young children.
I don't know.
Maybe I'm projecting, but I have to believe it affected him.
Well, maybe, but to the extent that it did,
he would have to say that's a failure
in my stoic self-tashing.
And, you know, he shouldn't, he should, it is that, I believe.
But of course, they're right about some things,
so it's not so simple.
They're right about not overestimating the role
of money in human life.
They're right about not overestimating the role
of reputation in human life. I love the about not overestimating the role of reputation in human life.
I love the part of date you're out where Sennaqa lectures himself and says, Oh, you left
the rudeness of this dorm and get to you.
And you were very offended.
And then when the hosts seated you at a lower place at the table, you were offended again.
He said, Stop that.
And I'll pardon you.
So, you know, those things, I think they're right about that.
So it's like they just don't want to get into the difficult work of making the discrimination
between things that really have worth and things that don't have worth.
They'd rather say none of the externals have worth, and then they don't have any hostages
to fortune.
Do you think they were afraid of compassion then?
And that was, that compassion was, you know,
opening Pandora's box or something,
because it seems to me that compassion and justice
are related to each other.
And in fact, compassion is what propels one sense
of justice, but they were trying not to see it that way.
It feels like.
They were.
Well, I don't know psychologically how they got there, but they started from the philosophical
position that no external goods have worth.
Only your inner world, which you allegedly control.
Now, of course, Aristotle had already cast out on that by
saying, if you imagine the sage on the rack, you can't imagine that that person is actually thinking
noble thoughts, the pain is too interactive with thought, but they did maintain that idea.
And, well, I think they just, it's not so much afraid. They thought compassion was part and parcel of a whole network of emotions, which were
mostly problematic.
So if you got rid of the ones that are obviously problematic, you have to get rid of that,
too.
And they were just afraid to make distinctions.
I mean, for example, they might have said, you shouldn't feel compassionate when somebody
loses a fortune.
That's not such a big deal.
That's not a real tragedy. That's not such a big deal. That's not a real tragedy.
That's a common day, maybe.
But you should feel compassion for somebody who's lost a child or a country or whatever else.
So they just didn't get into that fine tuning the way an Aristotelian would.
They just instead just said, junk, the whole thing.
Yes. just instead just said junk the whole thing. Yes, there is a sense of like if I don't think about it, if I don't care about it, then it's
that it won't affect me. But I would argue that by not being compassionate, by walling oneself off
from other people and the things that befall them, you actually are harming yourself.
You're closing yourself off.
You're losing touch with what makes you decent and good and just.
Well, I totally agree.
And I also think if you don't agree when you lose somebody that you love, well, that
means you never loved in the first place.
And that means your personality is dried up in some way. It's not deep. And I do think that grief
is an excruciatingly painful emotion, but it's also part of a deepening of the personality.
It's rededication to the value of things that are worth caring about, but they didn't agree.
They just said they're not worth caring about.
Yeah, there's this story about Marcus Aurelius.
He's young.
He hasn't fully sort of become the heart and staluck
that he becomes and he loses one of his tutors
and he's weeping and the story is that
one of his tutors goes to,
one of the other tutors goes and says,
hey, stop that, you know, that isn't staluck. And Antoninus says, let the boy be human for once. He says empire and philosophy
does not take away natural feeling. And I do think I think Antoninus who is more the intuitive
philosopher as opposed to the dogmatic or orthodox philosopher
has a better sense of, you know,
the middle ground there between being overwhelmed
and at the mercy of one's emotions
and shutting them off completely
and pretending that they don't exist.
Right, except that he puts it in terms
of natural human feelings.
And of course, that's part of what emotions are.
But I think we ought to cultivate the ability
to care deeply about things outside ourselves.
It isn't, we're not born with the love of our children.
We don't have children yet.
And you have to learn what it is to have a child
and what it is to love a child.
So I think it's part of an intelligent,
cultivated sense of the world.
No, I totally agree.
There's a quote, I forget who said it,
but it's something like, you know,
there are parts of you that you just can't understand
until you have loved a child.
And you can let that process open you up
or you can not let it open you up.
It's a choice.
I think cultivation is the right word there.
Where is this passage?
It's not from a philosopher.
It's more like a random quote you'd see on an inspirational website, I think.
But I love the quote.
I think it's certainly true.
And I think what's remarkable about Cicero is he does allow that love of
Cicero to open him to the fullness of grief. And then he greets that also to his grief for the
Republic. And he says to Atticus, well, you know, I don't really care what people are saying about
me not coming to the city because I can't stop grieving and furthermore, I don't think I ought to
stop grieving. And that powerful, great life, as you see from and furthermore, I don't think I ought to stop grieving.
And that powerful greet, as you see from my animals book, I identify with that deeply
because I lost my only child in 2019 when she was about the same age as Tullia when she died.
I'm so sorry.
And so I feel the same pain.
And I do think it is one of the most excruciating things one can experience. But you know, really,
it's important, deepening of your personality, and it's changed my work,
it's changed what I dedicate my life to because she was a lawyer for animal
rights. And I thought, well, what is this life? Well, it has, the
person is no longer there, but the commitments are still there.
And it's possible for me, although I can't get the person back to area her commitments on,
and make them vibrant, and make them live, and do good in the world.
So, yeah, I mean, it's something that grief revealed to me is what I must do next.
to next. When we think of sports stories, we tend to think of tales of epic on the field glory.
But the new podcast Sports Explains the World brings you some of the wildest and most surprising
sports stories you've never heard, like the teenager who wrote a fake Wikipedia page
for a young athlete and then watched as a real team fell for his prank.
And the mysterious secret of a US Olympic superstar killed at the peak of his career. Was it an accident? Did the police screw up the investigation?
It was also nebulous.
Each week, Sports Explains the World goes beyond leagues and stats to share stories that will
redefine your understanding of sports.
And their impact on the world.
Listen to Sports Explains the World, on the Wondering app or wherever you get your podcasts.
You can listen to Sports Explains the World early and add free on Wondering app or wherever you get your podcasts. You can listen to sports explains the world early
and ad-free on Wondering Plus.
Seneca does write his beautiful essays, his consolations.
And one thing that I always took from them,
he says, you know, how would the person
that you're missing want you to feel?
Would they want you to feel miserable
and be paralyzed with grief or would they want you to feel miserable and be paralyzed with grief or would they want
you to carry on and sort of follow their example.
But I do think that's quite beautiful to carry on that work in that legacy.
The answer is you shouldn't be deeply grieving.
And you should realize, well, it's a brief thing and you come right back to the city,
et cetera.
But that just isn't the way I think deep love translates into morning.
Morning, I mean, think about our recent guidelines in the US.
The morning is pathological after a certain number of months.
I forget how many Americans want to quick fix for life's problems.
Yes. And this one reason why they don't like cycle analysis, why they'd rather take a pill, number of months, I forget how many Americans want to quick fix for life's problems.
And this one reason why they don't like cycle analysis, why they'd rather take a pill,
anything that's wrong with you, you can cure with a pill. And that's just not the way life is. And if you think that way, you're just not going to have deep love in your life at all.
So let's talk about animals and the idea of justice.
I mean, I do feel like there is some kind of,
there's some basic framework,
there's something in the Stoics,
I think akin to like the way we might look
at the work of Jefferson,
where they had some noble ideas,
they put forth a framework that they were not even close
to living up to, but that we can find the truth in and try to expand and live better through.
I think of the work of Hierocles, for instance, the sort of circles of concern, the idea that sure were naturally kind of selfish and would care most about the people're related to or look like us or live near us.
But that the work of justice is how to,
to borrow Peter Singer's phrase,
how to sort of expand that circle
or bring those outer rings closer and closer to us.
Yes, I think that's a beautiful image that they have.
I don't think it's a complete guide
to how we should think, because of
course it allows us to be privileged toward our own species and toward our own relations.
And you know, there are some contexts in which that might make sense. I think that Siseroe
has powerful arguments that the republic should come first and you're thinking about political
distribution that you can't create a dressed world unless you start with your own republic because that's where you share citizenship
and that's where that's an order that's accountable to you.
But of course, even there, there are animals there.
Are they citizens or are they not?
And of course, as Sissarot didn't think they were,
but I think that in whatever unit you're starting with,
whether it's a city or even a family, the animals that are there are also citizens, and we ought
to think about them.
I do think that in terms of work for animals, it makes a lot of sense to start with the
local because you can control much more, and it's accountable to you.
So for example, our university has certain policies on child
experiments involving children, but we should have also policies involving animals on our campus.
Now there are policies on animal experimentation, but the child policy says that if anywhere on
your campus you see a child who's hungry, who doesn't have a coat,
then you must immediately phone the local department
of child and family services and report that
as an instance of child abuse.
I think there should be a similar department
of animal services so that if I were to see an abused dog
wandering across the midway, that's part of the campus, I would immediately call up this department and I would say there's an abused dog wandering across the midway, that's part of the campus. I would
immediately call up this department and I say there's an abused dog out there.
And I would have a place to report it right now, except for the most
horrible instances of, you know, dog rings and horrible dog abuse. There's not
much investigation going on. And if people are reusing their companion animals
or any other animals, nothing much is done about it.
Then there's no guardian of the animals who has standing
to bring a case in court on the animals behalf.
If a child with intellectual disabilities
is being abused, human beings have standing
to bring a lawsuit on that child's behalf.
There's no reason why the same arrangement
can't be made for animals as Cass Sunstein said in his famous article, Standing for Animals,
but you know, it just isn't happening in our country just yet. I do see signs of hope within
the country. So the recent Supreme Court case that allowed California to make stringent regulations of the confinement of pigs.
You know, California has the best animal welfare laws
in the country, and they pass laws saying that no pork
sold anywhere in California can be sold
if the animal is not in certain, certain conditions,
a certain amount of space to move around,
none of these so-called gestation crates
where the animal can't even lie down, has to urinate through metal slats and so forth.
So they banned all this stuff and then of course the pork industry didn't like that and
they brought suits saying California has no right to do that.
And even the Supreme Court said yes they do.
So federalism is good because then it sets up a kind of competition. And, of course,
it also means that Californians can't buy pork produced in Iowa that's produced under these bad
conditions. So, it sets norms that others have to obey. And it's really totally changed the
egg industry all over the country because the market in California is a very large market.
all over the country because the market in California is a very large market. For range ads are not terribly much more expensive to produce.
And so mostly now, everywhere you go, you find free range.
Eggs.
So, in short, I think both local and national law are the places where a concerned person
is wise to begin because we can do something about that.
At the end of my book, I talk about the weakness of international law. is wise to begin because we can do something about that.
At the end of my book, I talk about the weakness
of international law.
And of course, it's week all over the place.
Human rights laws, there are human rights treaties
out there, but who's going to enforce them?
Nobody, I mean, people are paying lip service
to those treaties.
And they're not enforced unless, in addition,
nations have passed statutes that incorporate them.
And with animals, well, the case I discussed is the International Committee on Whaling and the whales are governed by this international treaty.
But number one, the purpose of the treaty was to preserve enough whales so that people could hunt them down and harpoon
them. So it's really just conservation of what they call whales, stocks, as though the
whales are things in a store. And so, of course, with that beginning, you can't expect that
they're going to do very much about even about the cruelty in harpooning, which is getting
a little bit better regulated because gradually more humane people creep into that organization.
But then we see the terrible weakness, which is that only countries that voluntarily sign up are part of this group.
So Japan signed up and they were part of the group until they started to be told,
sorry, you can't hunt whales anymore. And then they just quit the group. So what
do you do about that? And it's very, very difficult, of course. And it's difficult for human
rights. But with human rights, you know, look at Biden claiming that with Uganda's terrible
new law on same-sex relations, he's actually going to use sanctions against that nation. And
I think he probably will. And then the country will probably support him in that
Because no one in the US actually supports these terrible laws not even conservatives
But what about it?
Ted Cruz talked about it. Oh really?
Yeah, well, it doesn't surprise me that much, but you know supposed
But on the other side somebody said well, let's subject to the treatment
of pigs in such and such country.
Well, of course, we need one of the worst abusers.
Anyway, American politicians are absolutely terrified of saying anything about the animal
issue at the national level.
Now, local, it's different.
In the city of Chicago, it's quite good on many things.
But only Cory Booker among politicians with the national ambition as a presidential candidate
has come out in favor of the defensive animal rights. And he is a vegan. And so I admire him
greatly because he's sticking his neck out. And he's basically like, sister, I was sticking his neck
out of the litter getting it chopped off because he's never
going to be a viable presidential candidate.
But the meat industry is so powerful.
If a lot of politicians came out,
then things would change.
But I remember a young friend of mine
who was an animal rights activist.
She was then around 12 years old.
She came up to Hillary Clinton when we met her after an event
and she said to Mrs. Clinton, what do you think of the animal rights?
Hillary Clinton turned pale and almost fainted and she said, oh well, I'm very in favor of human rights.
So you see the cowardice. She didn't want to touch the third rail.
No, she didn't want to touch it at all. She didn't want to say a thing. She didn't want to touch the third rail. No, she didn't want to touch it at all.
She didn't want to say a thing. She didn't want to say something bad. She didn't want to say
something good. So she just changed the subject. But Cory Booker is different and quite admirably
so, but it's not going to do him any good in national politics. In other countries, they're
actually even prime ministers, the former prime minister of
Ireland, the Baradkar, was a vegan, very much in favor of animal rights, and there are,
I think, politicians in Luxembourg in particular.
And all over Europe, there's much more support for animal protective laws, the laws that
they have are much, much better.
But the economics of the meat industry in the United States
is just so huge.
It's such a big part of America.
What they think, it's a big part of the American economy.
I don't agree.
I think it actually hurts the economy overall,
because it also, the minimal agriculture contributes
to global warming and all of this causes great trouble
for farmers and so forth.
But until we get a coalition
of politicians, farmers, humane animal razors, I'm doing an event shortly for a group of humane
farm in New England called sweet farm, and they want to say, you know, we haven't gone as,
they don't, haven't, don't go as far as me because I still think one should not eat these animals and kill them.
But they at least say we should give them a good life while they are alive.
So, you know, we need a coalition of many types of people.
And I'm not somebody who takes an extreme position and refuses to talk to people who have a less extreme position.
Anyone who wants to move the needle and Peter Singer is like this too.
He's willing to make a coalition
with people who don't agree with him.
So long as it will move the needle
from where we are to a better place.
Well, you have a quote in one of my books,
I wrote this book on stillness
and I have a chapter on what I would call oneness
and I wanted to read this quote that I took from an article you wrote,
which I thought was pretty beautiful.
You said, we share a planet with billions of other sentient beings,
and they all have their complex ways of being whatever they are.
All of our fellow animal creatures, as Aristotle observed long ago,
try to stay alive and reproduce more of their kind.
All of them perceive, all of them desire,
and most move from place to place
to get what they want and need.
I think there's something about trying to see,
obviously there's a problem with anthropomorphizing,
but we should try to see the commonality
that we have with animals,
and then that allows us to go,
well, how would I want to be treated
if I was in that position?
Or how would I feel if this was happening to me?
And sort of that extension of the golden rule
when we see our commonality between us and other species,
which is what I do think the Stoics were trying to do
with their early notions of cosmopolitanism
that borders and distinctions between people and races was largely artificial. They didn't quite
get there as far as doing anything about it, but they did try to see themselves in the other.
Yeah, absolutely. And so that idea of commonality is already an Aristotle.
I wrote my PhD dissertation on Aristotle's Des Motu Anomalium, a little treatise in which
he, without referring to any particular species, never re-singling out the human being, never
say irrational beings and non-rational beings, he actually shows that there is a commonality in how you explain
animal movement. They all move through some kind of thought, which might be sense perception,
it might be imagination, and it might be deliberative thought, and some form of desire,
which might be emotional desire, might be a petitive desire, it might be deliberative desire.
And so that's what he's doing in that little treatise.
And I've come back to that recently.
I'm about to go to Finland for a conference in memory of a great Aristotelian philosopher
Simo Knutila.
And so I decided I would revisit my doctoral dissertation and bring, they moved to Anomalia
into the present day.
And there has been recently a lot of work on it anyway,
because a great scholar in Germany, Prima Vasi,
did a new edition of the text,
and I've delighted to say that he found new manuscript
support for a conjecture that I had made long ago,
that there was a third independent manuscript family.
So I've worked with Prima Vasi a bit on this,
and he and Christoph Fra Robb have now edited this
great volume of the symposium Aristotelicum, which is a triennial meeting about an Aristotle
topic.
And this meeting was on De Motu, Alamaliam.
The book came out in 2020, so I'm just suggesting it now and I wrote this paper talking about
some of the new work on that treatise and the commonality.
But it's called Aristotle's Demo to Anomaly of Yesterday and Today, saying, well, you know,
there are things we might change about Aristotle. And of course, we must supply an ethical dimension
that doesn't show up in the Demo to Anomaly, and it's not an ethical work. But about the commonality, I guess the thing that
I would change is that I think he almost goes too far because he thinks that the stationary
animals like carls and sponges and so on are very similar. They're sentient beings just
like other animals. And I think the evidence shows that no, their movements are more like automata.
But anyway, there are just these things
that if he knew how to do the experiments we could do,
he would find grain, he'd fine-tune it a little bit more.
But boy, I think it's a big contribution
because a lot of scientists don't want
to come in explanation either, because they think,
oh, that will lead to phony anthropomorphism.
But there's phony anthropomorphism, but there's true commonality.
And that's what we have to find.
And so I really think Aristotle has a lot to show us.
How do you reconcile someone who's sort of progressive in the sense that they, he's
thinking about animals and what they're feeling and going through
and wanting to extend the notion of justice to them.
And then sort of also at that time,
okay, with slavery.
How do you, how do you think about that in the ancient world?
Well, yeah, I mean, how do you think about any of these things?
I think Aristotle, of course, what did he mean by natural slaves?
I think he doesn't mean the people who were conquered in battle,
and then enslaved as a result.
He says it has to be people from birth are unable to use their reason.
That would have to mean that there,
some sort of person with a lifelong
disability, and that they're born that way, and that would not be a whole race of people,
who would just have to be one by one.
And then how many such people are there that you could actually use to do all the heavy
labor on your estate?
So I don't know.
It's a weird passage, because it may be some people have thought it was a reductio of
the whole idea of
Enslabment but in any case, yeah, you you should not of course even if there's a being with a lifelong disability
You should not do bad things to that being and of course we know that Aristotle was in favor of in phantoside of disabled
Children so so at least that we need to get rid of. And of course, the people who think these invoke Aquinas, and they think that the whole ancient rural was against abortion.
Not only are they wrong about abortion, Aristotle thought abortion is fine up until the sixth month, but they also inserted in it, by the way. But they also thought that there's nothing wrong
with infanticide post-birth if the child has a serious disability.
So there are all these things that we have to get rid of.
And of course, we have to especially get rid
of their terrible denigration of women
and the role of women in the world and in the economy and so forth.
And there, the Stoics are actually dead because they're so rationalists that they don't
care what kind of body somebody has.
But so for the wrong reasons, they treat women a bit better.
But I think we just have to do it differently.
We have to think that the body is dignified and each body has its own dignity and must not
be abused whether it's human or from another species.
Yeah, the subtitle of your book, I think, is really interesting.
You say, our collective responsibility.
This idea of there being a common good
and that we all have an obligation to each other,
particularly to the lesser or the most vulnerable.
To me, that's the essence of what justice is,
and that's kind of what,
maybe this is a perversion of it a little bit,
but what I think on clemency is really about,
is it's saying that how you treat the people
or the things that can't do anything for you,
but you have power over.
That says everything about who you are.
That's very nicely put.
I think the way I talked about the collective responsibility
started from the fact that there are a lot of people
in philosophy, a lot of very good philosophers
who are largely Kantians who think that if there's a rights then you
must be able to assign duties to some definite specific actor and of Nora O'Neil for
example has said this and so if they're if you can't assign the duties to this or
that particular person then there are no rights. Now here I'm with Christine
Korzart I don't agree with her on everything but she's the kind of Kantian that I
can agree with if they may come and with. And in her wonderful book,
Fellow Creatures, she says that we have to start with the fact that the arguments in favor of
rights that a Kantian would give, namely starting from your right to be where you are, we have to
conclude that other creatures also have the right to be where they are.
Especially if they were there first.
Yeah, well, and it entails control of property, so the right to be where you are is very broad.
And then the question is to whom do we assign the duties relative to these rights?
And she then says what I say.
Well, we can't yet assign it to particular individuals because legal systems
are in their infancy, but we can say all humanity has a collective obligation to protect these rights.
And this is to me the some of the progress we're making, whether, you know, first off,
just to think that the invention of, say, natural parks and national monuments and wildlife
preserves are relatively new, right, as far as inventions go.
We're talking about Aristotle and Marcus Aurelius, the idea that, you know, we would protect
the grazing land of a buffalo or something.
These are relatively recent innovations in how we think about things.
I think that's really beautiful.
But now some of these things like wildlife corridors or wildlife bridges, there's one
in here in Texas.
Like, hey, mountain lions want to cross over this.
Or coyotes want to cross over this.
And if we're going to build a highway through their places of travel, then we have to provide
means for them to get across too, just as we do for cars and pedestrians and semi-trucks.
Yeah, absolutely.
And this is a place where law has a lot to do.
And in fact, one of the things my daughter was working on,
and she worked for an NGO that dealt with the rights
of not domesticated animals but wild animals.
And she was dealing with wild horses.
And they have exactly that problem
that they exist in Wyoming, they exist in Colorado.
But they need corridors.
And of course the ranchers don't like the creation
of these corridors because they want to use them
for grazing their cattle.
So there's a constant combat between the ranchers
and the wild horses, and then the ranchers say,
oh well, let's call the wild horses, there are too many of them.
So it's an endless battle, but yes, wildlife has property rights. And
there's a very good book that one of my students wrote recently, University of Chicago Press,
about animal property rights. So I cite that in the book. And yeah, there's a lot of work to be done.
It is interesting. You brought up federalism earlier earlier how you do need strong central governments
or legal systems to be able to enforce these things?
I mean, one of the reasons slavery lasts so long, particularly in the U.S., but Britain
has a little more success with it early on, there's this argument that, hey, I'm legally
allowed to do this thing.
So if you're going to, and now, but now you're insisting that these people have rights or
this thing has rights, that infringes on my rights or my property or my bank balance.
And you do need a government to step in and say, well, okay, fine, we'll compensate
you if a wolf eats your cow, right?
You need mechanisms and you need the sense
of collective responsibility to deal with the individuals
who are negatively impacted by the elevation
of previously disenfranchised or unprotected species or organisms.
Yep, that's very good.
If you think about the 19th century, children were thought to be the property of their parents.
And when people started to introduce laws for compulsory education of young children,
the parents of all things got very upset.
They said our survive.
How are we going to support ourselves?
Using the children for child labor.
So eventually, of course, the limits on child labor
that got better and better, but the compulsory education
was a huge step.
And so that's how it goes.
You have to fight for people who just imagine parents
thinking I would rather use my child for hard labor
than I would give the child an education.
People don't think that way today.
But the reason they stop thinking that way is that visionary people, and in fact the British
Liberal Party actually split over this issue, TH Green, the philosopher was in the vanguard,
and he actually was a Liberal Party politician.
They stuck their next out, and they really went to bat for these abused children
and the same thing has to be done with animals. And I think, you know, look at what California
has been able to do by forming public opinion in a certain way. Here in Chicago, we've
made a lot of progress. One issue I talk about is puppy mills. People think, oh, I'm going
to buy a cute little puppy
and they don't ask where it's coming from.
But there are these immoral breeders.
And unfortunately, most of them are located in the state of Missouri.
It happens.
And Missouri, because they're located there and they have great political power, Missouri
doesn't control them.
So you can't control them at the point of origin.
They're bringing up these puppies with parasites,
diseases, not enough room to move around.
And then they market them while they're so cute and young
in pet shop, sold over the country.
So at least a point of sale, you can control that.
It's much harder than if you could regulate
at the point of origin.
But Chicago has actually cracked down on that by saying,
the only kind of animal you may purchase, and
it's really a kind of an option, is a former shelter animal, and the pet stores, so
called, would be in the business of giving for a nominal fee, those of you as animals.
Then the puppy male people re-costume themselves as shelters.
There were a whole bunch of bogus shelters and they would say,
oh, here's the rescue dog, but it was really a puppy
builder.
So eventually they had to make a law against that too.
So it's a constant vigilance and constant work.
And I have great respect for the alderman Brian Hopkins
who watched out for that issue.
He really made that his issue.
And, you know, it's hard if you're a politician because it's not terribly popular.
But of course, it doesn't solve the whole problem because somebody can, you know, the Missouri
people can sell it in some other town that doesn't have good laws.
People can drive out to the town if they really want it.
But in the process, the public gets educated.
And I think the main thing that we have to do is to raise the consciousness of humanity.
And I do feel that's happening.
It's hard and it takes a long time.
But law contributes to that, even though law is a perfect solution.
Well, do you think that's another area that perhaps stoicism falls short or the more fundamentalist
or dogmatic view of stoicism falls short, which is, okay, let's say buying a puppy from
a puppy mill or eating factory-formed meat.
Let's say that's a, you extend out stoicism to say that's a matter of justice.
So the stoic would say, well, what's in my control?
I am not going to participate in that system. I'm not going to eat at Chick-fil-A. I'm not going to buy
pure bread, puppy milled dog. I'm not going to participate. But there's something
woefully insufficient about simply looking at these matters. And so as far as our individual contribution to them goes,
a lot of these problems, the matters of justice for our time
whether we're talking about genocide or pandemics or animal rights,
these are collective action issues.
And I sometimes wonder how stoicism can operate in that in that domain.
It can't just be I'm not going to get my I'm not going to contribute to it myself. You have to do
something about it. I think that's totally right. And I think about Cicero again, his best friend, Atticus, was not a stoic, but an epicurean,
but on this issue, they have a similar view.
Namely, the epicurean thought, don't get involved
in politics, too much anxiety, too much fear.
And Atticus slipped all the way through the civil wars.
He was a wealthy banker, so everyone
wanted him to be healthy and rich.
And he didn't really stick his neck out to save Cicero.
He intervened only when he thought it was low cost.
He was Cicero's best friend,
and I think it was a wonderful friendship,
but I sometimes wonder what did Cicero really think
about that way of life?
And it's just not the right way of life
in a time of trouble.
That doesn't mean that everyone should be on the front, that aligns there many, many
ways that people can contribute to progress on an issue.
People can contribute by bringing up children who have refined ethical consciousness about
animals.
They can teach about the wonderful abilities of animals.
They can have dialogues with their colleagues.
I've just been exchanging views on this with a colleague
who really didn't think very much about the abilities
of animals, and then she said to me,
well, it wasn't amazing what abilities animals have.
So, you know, but my chosen mode is one that I feel
is good for me,
namely writing and arguing.
And then of course after that you go and get from talks
like this talk and try to spread the word
because writing the book is not any good
unless somebody reads the book.
But of course that's just my profession.
And I teach courses too.
I've developed at our law school.
I've developed a scholarship.
In fact, in Dow, the scholarship for a student,
particularly interested in animal law.
And we're just starting that this year.
But I've also developed a curriculum on animal law.
I'm going to teach a new course next year.
That will be for all first-year law students on animal law.
But it will be across.
So there will be philosophy students in there as well.
And that's what I can also do,
is send the word out.
I gave the book as a seminar before it was finished.
And the students who were in that seminar
really gave me a lot of help in refining the book.
And now they're graduating.
But they're going to do good things.
So they got good jobs and big offers.
But one of them, who was my research assistant,
said, I'm not going to accept your offer
to this big New York offer, unless you tell me what
I could do for animals in this job.
And they said, well, we do a lot of pro bono work.
And if you can design it, we'll
allow you to do of pro bono work. And if you can design it, we'll allow you to do a pro bono
program with some humane organization that helped them out. So this is the way these things
happen that people can't go out into the world and they don't necessarily give their whole
life to animal welfare, but they insist their firm has got to do the, it's part. And I think
that's how things change.
Yeah, there's a I think it was Emerson was talking about Clarkson, the abolitionist, and he said, the entire movement is the shadow of one man. And you know, one person pushing forward ideas,
your coaching tree of all of your students and what they go on to do, all your readers, what they go on to do.
This has a profound impact.
It changes the culture, it changes the laws slowly and steadily.
And it might not be, it's not the emperor snapping their finger
and radically changing all of the laws.
That's not our system anymore.
It's a more organic and incremental form of progress,
but it's a powerful one.
But the good thing about books is
they're not limited to the place where you are.
And I don't have to travel all over the world
because now I can do these lectures online.
That's one good thing.
But the book has been translated already within only a year into five languages and they're
more coming.
And it's been on the front page of Times of India.
India, of course, has a more elevated consciousness of animal welfare.
And it's one of the few nations in which animals do have legal standing.
So they're in advance and so forth.
But in any case, it was nice to be on the front page of the Times of India.
For this issue, and I hope that that was spread the word, you know, just wake up people
who might be more curious to find out what somebody like me would have to say.
But I think it's important that you're saying this because there is an imperative to get involved
and make a contribution.
I write this email every day, the Daily Stoic email,
which goes out to about 600,000 people.
And sometimes I'll talk about the political issues
of the day, whether it's women's rights or gay rights
or speaking out about political violence
or speaking about this stoic idea of justice.
And I'll sometimes get emails from people and they'll say, please stay away from these things.
I'll say you're alienating some of your audience. Don't you know I think differently about this?
They go, what would the what would the stoics say about you getting political? And I go, look,
the stoics were not perfect. But the one thing they were is political.
They held political office.
They engaged in the polis.
They spoke out about the things they thought that mattered of the time.
And in many cases, we're willing to give not just their voice to an issue, but in the
case of St. Cato, give their lives to set issue.
And I think the lives of the Stoics
show us that justice isn't just this thing you pay lip service to, but that you have
to see it as a, as an obligation to responsibility and you have to take action. You have to participate,
even if that's as simple as something is voting, you have to participate. It's not just
your individual behaviors that matter, but the actions that you take.
Absolutely. I'm not sure it's entirely consistent with their stoicism. You started out with my pump
kinification translation, and you know what I think about that. The Stenica there betrays a very
emotional commitment to political justice that is not consistent with his stoicism.
But anyway, whatever we think about this consistency or an inconsistency, right, these people did stick their neck out.
I like Cicero better because he says, well, it's not fully consistent, but it's what I must do.
And I do feel it's very, very important for faculty to do these things because we're
very privileged people.
Are you teaching someplace?
Nope, just a private citizen.
Well, anyway, we who teach in tenured positions, wow, are we privileged?
We get to spend a whole of our lives doing what we love and engaging with wonderful young
people. And so I think, oh, the world's some return on that.
And I really, you know, certain books that I write are because I love writing them.
I'm writing a book about music now, you know, and I'm writing another book about opera.
But there's some books that I write, both because I love them and because I feel it's my duty to write
and then wake people up on some issue.
To whom much is given, much is expected. If you have protected employment, how could you not use
that to speak out on behalf of people who don't have the same protections? Right.
Or security. Absolutely. Well, I think we need to wrap up pretty soon
only because you're almost one o'clock. So I just want to say this has been a great pleasure.
It's so nice to talk about the stoics and you obviously know a lot about Marcus more than I know
because I've never actually worked a whole lot on Marcus. So it's been a lot of. Well, I have learned
a lot about Seneca from your writings,
and I think you're doing very important work,
and I think it's important that we, yeah,
we don't, the distinction, which Seneca talks about,
between the Stoics and the Epicurians,
the idea that one gets involved because they feel compelled to,
and the other, he says, only gets involved if they have to.
You know, I think that's the distinction or the choice that we all have to make with the
issues of our day.
Yeah, well, I think that's right.
I love teaching the Stoics because all these issues come up in the class and they're among
the most living of all the philosophers that I teach.
Well, Professor, it's an honor.
Thank you so much for all your work.
It's a very, very pleasure. I really enjoyed it, Professor, it's an honor. Thank you so much for all your work. It's a great pleasure. I really enjoyed it, usually.
Thanks so much for listening. If you could rate this podcast and leave a review on iTunes,
that would mean so much to us and it would really help the show. We appreciate it,
and I'll see you next episode.
Hey, Prime Members. You can listen to the Daily Stoke early and ad-free on Amazon Music, download the Amazon Music app today, or you can listen early and ad-free with Wondery Plus
in Apple podcasts.
download the Amazon Music app today, or you can listen early and add free with
Wondery Plus in Apple podcasts.