Theories of Everything with Curt Jaimungal - Reality, God, Consciousness | Donald Hoffman Λ Philip Goff
Episode Date: December 19, 2023Donald Hoffman, cognitive scientist, and Philip Goff, philosopher, discuss consciousness, evolution, perception, and panpsychism. Insights into the nature of reality.YouTube Link: https://www.youtube....com/watch?v=MmaIBxkqcT4 TIMESTAMPS:00:00 - Intro02:46 - Goff’s World View11:39 - Do Neurons Exist?28:30 - What Is Real?39:22- Objections to Hoffman’s Views58:45 - Evolution1:37:19 - Reductionism1:49:38 - Meaning Of Life2:01:32 - Infinite Consciousness2:05:40 - Multiverse2:15:25 - Outro NOTE: The perspectives expressed by guests don't necessarily mirror my own. There's a versicolored arrangement of people on TOE, each harboring distinct viewpoints, as part of my endeavor to understand the perspectives that exist. THANK YOU: To Mike Duffey for your insight, help, and recommendations on this channel. - Patreon: / curtjaimungal (early access to ad-free audio episodes!) - Crypto: https://tinyurl.com/cryptoTOE - PayPal: https://tinyurl.com/paypalTOE - Twitter: / toewithcurt - Discord Invite: / discord - iTunes: https://podcasts.apple.com/ca/podcast... - Pandora: https://pdora.co/33b9lfP - Spotify: https://open.spotify.com/show/4gL14b9... - Subreddit r/TheoriesOfEverything: / theoriesofeverything - TOE Merch: https://tinyurl.com/TOEmerch LINKS MENTIONED: - Why? The Purpose of the Universe (Philip Goff): https://amzn.to/3TBXl1M - The Case Against Reality (Donald Hoffman): https://amzn.to/4airlWu - Galileo's Error (Philip Goff): https://amzn.to/482bg5Q - Consciousness and Fundamental Reality (Philip Goff): https://amzn.to/3RvPKzq - Mind Chat (Goff's podcast): / @mindchat - Podcast w/ Donald Hoffman on TOE: • Donald Hoffman: The Nature of Conscio... - Podcast w/ Daniel Dennett: COMING SOON • Theories of Everything with Curt Jaim... - Analysis of Matter (Bertrand Russell): https://amzn.to/3GPr1RE - A Brief History of Time (Stephen Hawking): https://amzn.to/41wH8gn - Debunking Interface Theory (Geoffrey Bagwell): https://philpapers.org/rec/BAGDIT - Quantum Bayesianism (Chris Fuchs): https://amzn.to/48nE3la - Fitness Beats Truth (Donald Hoffman): https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/33231784 - Podcast w/ John Vervaeke Λ Donald Hoffman on TOE: • Exposing the Matrix: Cognitive Scient... - Podcast w/ Joscha Bach Λ Donald Hoffman on TOE: • Donald Hoffman Λ Joscha Bach: Conscio... - Podcast w/ Bernardo Kastrup on TOE: • Escaping the Illusion: Bernardo Kastr... - Debate with Sean Carroll and Philip Goff: • Sean Carroll & Philip Goff Debate 'Is... - Classic Paper on Fine-Tuning (Roger White, 2000): https://web.mit.edu/rog/www/papers/fi... - Debate between Philip and Don on Philip's channel: • S03E06 What is Reality?
Transcript
Discussion (0)
Every scientific theory is only a projection of the truth. It's never the truth. No scientific
theory can ever be a theory of everything. What does it mean as a philosopher interested
in the ultimate nature of reality that our basic science is just equations?
We're not seeing the truth. Evolution is an artifact.
Our basic science isn't really telling us that much about what fundamental reality is.
really telling us that much about what fundamental reality is.
Professor Donald Hoffman and Professor Philip Goff are both renowned in their respective fields of cognitive science and philosophy. Hoffman is a cognitive scientist who has put forward a theory
called the Interface Theory of Perception, which states that human perceptions are akin to some
user interface shaped more by evolutionary survival imperatives
than by an accurate representation of the external world.
Thus, according to Hoffman, reality as we know it is some illusion.
In contrast, professor of Durham University, Philip Goff, is known for panpsychism,
and so there's plenty of contrasting agreement in different words in today's theolocution,
as well as disagreements, primarily around the universe's fine-tuning for life, as well as suggesting that, hey,
they both agree consciousness is fundamental, but that doesn't mean that what's derived from
consciousness is illusory. Quite the contrary. Philip has just published a book called Why?
The Purpose of the Universe, and the links to that are in the description, as well as his previous
works, Galileo's Error and Consciousness in Fundamental Reality. Even though Professor Goff is known for panpsychism, his views are best described as
cosmopsychism. This means that the universe itself might be a conscious entity with its own goals.
My name is Kurt Jaimungal. If you're new to this channel, this is Theories of Everything,
where we explore theories of everything, primarily from a physics perspective,
that is an analytical one, but as well as trying to understand, okay, if there is no TOE, if there is no theory of everything,
why?
That to me counts as its own, a limiting theory of everything.
Or perhaps a theory of a thing, what constitutes some thing as separate from another thing,
we've explored that with Carl Friston and Michael Levin, as well as what is free will,
how do we know if we have it, what are alternatives to compatibilism and libertarian notions?
And of course, how are we conscious?
That is the hard problem of consciousness.
Solutions to that. Is it idealism?
Is there something to Cartesian dualism or some other form of dualism?
How about a triadic model?
All of these are explored in depth with rigor on this channel
by interviewing some of the top intellectuals in this space.
If that sounds interesting to you, then feel free to subscribe
as we have two-hour, three-hour,, four hour, sometimes even eight hour long podcasts with
a guest. There are also clips released every single day. There's a new video. So if those
Rob Dingnangian podcasts are a bit too much, well, hey, get a teaser by listening to a five minute
section or a 10 minute section. Either way, enjoy this theolocution with Philip Goff and Donald
Hoffman. Okay, well, it's an honor to host you both. Thank you, Professor Goff. Either way, enjoy this theolocution with Philip Goff and Donald Hoffman.
Okay, well, it's an honor to host you both. Thank you, Professor Goff. Thank you,
Professor Hoffman, Hoff and Goff. Thank you, Kurt. Prof Hoff and Prof Goff, great to be here.
So, Prof Goff, you have a book that's recently been released called Why? What is it about? And please tell myself and the audience the relevance of it for this discussion.
they have to fit into the dichotomy of either you believe in the God of traditional Western religion or you're a secular atheist. It feels like you've got to say, whose side are you on,
Richard Dawkins or the Pope? And I was raised Catholic and decided I didn't believe in God
when I was about 14 and gave that one up and was quite happily on Team Secular Atheist for over 20 years.
But just recently, I've slowly come to think that both of these worldviews are inadequate.
Both of them have things they can't explain about reality.
And ultimately, where I think the evidence points is is to what i call cosmic purpose namely some kind of
goal-directedness at the fundamental level of reality but existing in the absence of
of the traditional god so so yeah so basically in this book that's why the purpose of the universe
got a very cool cover actually i'm pleased with what they did with
that and um i argue for this position and then discuss its implications for the meaning and
purpose of human existence so yeah so just basically very brief overview um you know one
one of the one of the things i think the traditional atheist picture of a meaningless, purposeless universe struggles to explain is the fine tuning of physics for life.
The recent discovery that for life to be possible, certain numbers in physics had to be against improbable odds just right.
And, you know, for a long time, I thought the multiverse was the best explanation for this.
long time i thought the multiverse was the best explanation for this but i've just been slowly persuaded by philosophers of probability that there's some dodgy reasoning in in in the inference
from fine-tuning to a multiverse that it commits what's called the inverse gambler's fallacy and
and so i've just been led to think that actually in our standard Bayesian ways of thinking about evidence, the fine-tuning just is evidence for cosmic purpose, for this kind of goal-directedness towards life.
And that's kind of weird. And I think as a society, we're sort of in denial about this at the moment because it doesn't fit with the picture of science we've got used to.
at the moment because it doesn't fit with the picture of science we've got used to it's maybe a bit like in the 16th century when we started getting evidence that we weren't in the center
of the universe and people struggled to accept that because it didn't fit with the version of
reality they'd got used to and now we sort of scoff at those people we thought they stupid
religious people why didn't they just follow the evidence but i think every generation absorbs a world view it can't see beyond and i think something like
that's going on uh with fine tuning right now um so it's not it's not it's not just
fine tuning on my case for cosmic purpose is built on there's also chapter on consciousness
and the mind body problem connecting
to ai and the science of consciousness and i think certain things in this area also point to cosmic
purpose although the argument there is a little bit takes a little bit longer to lay out so that's
so that's the case for kind of cosmic purpose now most people arguing for cosmic purpose
go for god god's fine-tuned the universe or something. But I don't like that hypothesis either. And here it's the familiar reason that the difficulty of reconciling an all-loving, omnipotent God with the terrible, gratuitous suffering we find in the world you know i just don't it doesn't make sense to me that
a loving god who could do anything you know would create a universe with so much pain so basically i
think atheists can't explain fine tuning and some consciousness stuff theists can't explain suffering
we need a hypothesis that can account for both of these data points. And just very, very finally,
just the style of the book is, you know, so my first book, which is somewhere here,
was an academic book. My second book, Galileo's Era, was aimed at a general audience. So this
book, I'm trying to do both. So it's with a academic press, Oxford University Press, so it's kind of properly peer-reviewed. But it's also set up as a trade book, so it's reasonably priced, unlike academic
books. But also each chapter has a more accessible bit and then a digging deeper bit, which goes into
some of the more technical details and all the objections and so on. So yeah, so maybe it'll
please no one, but I'm uniquely trying to appeal to both of those audiences. But yeah, that's about it really.
Sorry, that was a bit long winded.
Wonderful. And what is it that you appreciate about Don's work?
Oh, I'm a huge fan of Don's work. I mean, I think Don is a radical pioneer. You know,
I think humans always think that at the end of history and, you know i think humans always humans always think they're at the end of history
and you know that the current paradigm is basically established and the task is just to fill in fill
in the details and i think in every period most people go along with that you largely because you
look a bit people look at you funny if you don't but But I think, you know, Don has come up with some profound challenges to our prevailing materialist paradigm. And he's done so not just with science and mathematics, but also I think with engagement with philosophy.
scientistic period where people think all questions can be answers with experiments and they've forgotten the role of philosophy, the very important role of philosophy in the project of
finding out about reality. And I think, especially with consciousness, it's so important for science
and philosophy to work hand in glove. And it's just wonderful to see that in Don's work. And
yeah, it's stimulated me a great deal.
Don?
Thank you, Philip.
What is it you appreciate about Philip's work?
Well, I actually wrote a little blurb for his wonderful new book, and I think it's an outstanding book.
It's easily accessible to an average non-scientist, non-philosopher, but it's also something that a scientist and a
philosopher will find quite grabbing and challenging. So, it's brilliant to be able to
write about such deep issues in a way that the average non-scientist and philosopher
can understand and yet engages everybody else. So hats off to Philip for a remarkable book
and for doing that. And also just for the way he engages with very difficult questions and is not
afraid to go against the standard views where he thinks that he needs to go against them. And
that's not easy to do in academia. It's just not easy to do. And especially in philosophy, it's very, very difficult.
In science, you might be able to say, well, I've got a theorem.
So, you know, come at me because I've got a theorem.
Whereas it's a little harder.
I mean, sometimes you can have a logical proof in philosophy.
But short of that, then it just is a lot of bravery to go out there and say, here's a different point of view.
And then to take all the comers.
And so, hats off to Philip for doing that.
And I must say that I really enjoyed learning a lot about the philosophical issues in his latest book, Why.
So, that's very, very helpful.
And one thing that philosophers do is remind scientists to think about our basic core concepts, to look at the
logical structure of what we're thinking about, not just jump in with the mathematics and go off
and compute and so forth and derive consequences, but to think at a fundamental level about the
very concepts that we're using at the foundations of our theories and to think about that conceptually.
And so I really appreciate Philip pushing me around in the conceptual space on the on the very topics that
that that i've been engaged with for decades so that's again much appreciated thanks so much tom
i know you have a question for i know you both have several questions for one another
and i'll just state one of them to you, Don, and then we'll hear your answer,
and then you'll ask the same question to Philip. The question is about neurons and whether they
exist prior to being perceived, and same with space-time and elementary particles.
So you'd like me to answer my own question first?
Yeah, what is your point of view on that? And then we'll get Philip's answer.
Right. So first I'll say what I think the standard view is, so I can contrast my view with the standard view, which most of my colleagues in cognitive neuroscience just take it for granted that, of course, are responsible for conscious experiences in humans and perhaps other animals as well.
And maybe if you have the right programming and circuits and software of some AI, it'll eventually be conscious as well.
So, this approach to consciousness that says neurons exist when they're not perceived and neural activity
is responsible for the generation of consciousness, I think runs afoul of modern science,
modern physics in particular. The Nobel Prize in 2022, last year, was awarded to three physicists
for confirming experimentally what quantum theory seems to predict theoretically
that local realism is false.
The local realism is the claim that, well, locality, realism is the claim that objects
have definite values or properties like position and momentum and spin when they're not observed.
So the electron has a position even if no one looks.
And locality is just the particles obey Einstein's space-time laws.
Things can't travel faster than the speed of light influences.
So local realism is false.
And I think that we should recognize that local realism is false. Neurons simply
don't exist. Well, put it this way, they don't have any position when they're not observed.
And if something doesn't have a position, it's not there, right? If you don't have a position,
you're not there. So, I would say that neurons simply, that right now, I don't have any neurons.
And someone who's hearing my argument might say, yes, I completely agree with you now, that you don't have any neurons.
But I'm saying I don't have any neurons.
If you opened up someone's skull, you would find neurons, but you would be creating them on the fly when you observed.
which you would be creating them on the fly when you observed.
And that's, again, in line with what quantum theory says,
is that these particle properties emerge in the act of observation,
and they're a result of the observation, but they do not exist prior to the observation. And there are, by the way, in quantum theory cases where you can set up empirical experimental situations where you can prove that the,
if you make a certain measurement, you'll get a certain outcome with probability one.
And you can also prove that that outcome could not possibly be there until you made the observation.
So I'll say that again.
You can prove in these special,
and if you want to see the paper on this, it's Chris Fuchs, his 2010 paper on quantum
Bayesianism. He goes into this. So you don't have to rely on me. You can read that paper and read
for yourself. A quantum experiment that gives you a case where you can prove that you will,
if you make this particular measurement, get a certain value with probability one.
Probability one.
But you can also prove, given the detailed setup of the situation, that it's impossible,
logically impossible, that the value of that outcome existed prior to the measurement.
So this is what you can set up in quantum theory. And that's why a lot of people realize that local realism is false.
And it took the Nobel Committee decades before they gave the Nobel Prize for it because this is a big one.
Clauser did a lot of work decades ago, and then they were tightening, tightening, tightening, closing the loopholes and so forth.
And finally, the Nobel Committee said, okay, what can we do?
So, I think that it's just in keeping with what physics is telling us to let go of local realism for neurons.
And so I would say no.
Neurons do not exist when they're not perceived.
Philip?
Yeah, so I think Don and I have more in common than that divides us.
Crucially, our fundamental starting point is that consciousness
exists at the fundamental level of reality. Well, I don't know if it's a starting point,
but it's a crucial aspect of our view. I suppose where this first question gets to the heart
of maybe where we disagree, namely on the status of physical reality. So I think Don, he can speak for himself,
but defends a view that philosophers have traditionally called idealism, which usually
comes with the idea that the physical world is illusory in some sense or not fully real.
Whereas I guess I'm more inclined to the view that the physical world is
entirely real and independent of our minds. You know, this, this Batman cup is really out there
in the world and lights bouncing off it. And, uh, you know, it's made up of particles or fields or
whatever. It's just that those particles and fields are ultimately made up of consciousness
in ways we could perhaps get into. And I suppose that the reason I'm there is, yeah, I mean,
I'm totally open to Don's position. So I suppose my view is sort of, I suppose, in a way, a middle,
I always go for the middle ways, a middle way between the physicalist or materialist position
and the idealist position.
I'm open to Don's position, but I suppose I'm just not totally as yet persuaded by his arguments, as intriguing as they are. Don often appeals to these speculative theories in, or, you know,
popular, not fringe at all, popular theories, uh, in theoretical physics,
according to which space and time don't exist at the fundamental level of reality. They're rather
emergent, but, um, I, well, we recently, I organized a conference on panpsychism in the
States and Don kindly gave a talk and, um, Sean Carroll was the the the in-house skeptic of all this business and um and and sean
sean's response to one of sean's wants to don that kind of agree with is you know just because
space and time don't exist at the fundamental level of reality doesn't mean they're not real
right it's um uh you know we discovered atoms are not fundamental they're made up of uh you know
quarks and electrons that doesn't mean we say oh there's no atoms you know we just say that they're
not fundamental so yeah so i'm not on the local realism i mean this is going to quickly get
outside of my skill set but you know my understanding talking to people like tim
maudlin um is not the is that yeah none of this rules out for the bohmian view for example although
i know that's not an incredibly popular view but even if you go for um a more popular interpretation
of quantum mechanics yeah i mean we don't have to crudely think particles are the fundamental
things it could be you know the wave function is the fundamental physical reality um sean carroll tells me believes
in the fundamental reality as a vector in high dimensional hilbert space um so we could have
some some esoteric uh fundamental physical reality but which which three-dimensional space and time
emerges from you know this is a heated debate in philosophy of physics. some the more non-space-time esoteric maybe quantum wave function reality that physicists
currently are inclined to think is at the fundamental level of reality so yeah so maybe
the normal world we perceive is is real but emergent don it would be useful at this point
to characterize the definition of real great points philip. Of course, great points. So, the word real, right? We use the word
real in a couple different senses, and so maybe we want to distinguish a couple of senses of real.
So, one version of real is something is real if it exists even when it's not perceived.
And I think that's what perhaps you were saying. But there's another sense in which
something is real. For example, if I have a headache and I complain about this nasty headache
that I've got, that headache wouldn't exist if I didn't perceive it, right? So my headache isn't
real in the sense that I just gave before, that it would exist even if it weren't perceived.
And nevertheless, someone might say, well, if you don't say my headache is real,
I beg to differ you. My headache is real. So, there's a sense in which something is real if
it's a real subjective experience. And in that case, we know that the word, we're saying something's
real not because it exists even when it's not perceived, but rather it exists in
my perception. And so, the question about are neurons real is I'm really asking are they real
in the sense that they would exist even if they're not perceived? And I think your answer is yes,
they are real in the sense that they would exist even if they're not perceived.
And I'm saying no, that they're only real in the sense that they are subjective experiences that we have.
And so they exist while we have the experience and they don't exist otherwise.
Okay, so just that notion of real because people can wobble on that and get confused on what we're discussing. So then, my take on it is,
of course, physicists are going to debate, and Sean Carroll doesn't think that we need to worry about
space-time is doomed.
So we'll have to see where the physics goes in this. But here's what I see
happening in the last 10 years.
For the high-energy theoretical physicists who are working on this, they're finding that space-time – so what they argue is that space-time is doomed because it has no operational meaning at 10 to the minus 33 centimeters, the Planck scale.
It's not that there are pixels at 10 to the minus 33 centimeters. It'sck scale. And it's not that there are pixels at 10 to the
minus 33 centimeters, it's that space-time makes no sense anymore. There's nothing you can do
operationally with it. And from my point of view, it's a fairly shallow data structure.
It falls apart at 10 to the minus 33 centimeters. Not 10 to the minus 33 trillion centimeters,
just 10 to the minus 33. And it's useless after that. And 10 to the minus 33 trillion centimeters, just 10 to the minus 33. And it's useless after that.
And 10 to the minus 43 seconds, not 10 to the minus 43 trillion seconds, 10 to the minus 43.
So it's a fairly shallow data structure. And so in the last 10 years, physicists have been saying,
well, what happens if we let go of space-time completely and also quantum theory completely and look for some deeper structures beyond space-time and, and also quantum theory completely, and look for some deeper
structures beyond space-time and quantum theory. Can we find anything that can actually do work,
like predict scattering amplitudes of particle collisions in the Large Hadron Collider and so
forth? And in the last 10 years, so this is all relatively new, they've discovered that,
yes, you can, that you can actually, there are these new structures like the decorator permutations and amplituhedra that lets you compute actual scattering processes in spacetime.
And they have two advantages.
What they've discovered are two advantages over spacetime physics.
over space-time physics.
One is that,
first, if you do it inside space-time using quantum field theory,
just to compute one interaction
like two gluons hitting each other
and four gluons spraying out
is hundreds of pages of algebra
and millions of terms.
It's a mess
because you're doing it all on quantum fields
and space-time.
You're enforcing quantum theory
and relativity theory.
When you let go of space-time
and these new structures, you can do what was millions of terms in three or four or five terms.
You can compute it by hand. So the math all of a sudden becomes simple. Well, simpler. Physics is
never easy, but simpler. And the second thing is you see new symmetries. There's something that
they call the infinite Yang-Yin symmetry, which you cannot see in space-time. But when you let go of space-time, all of a sudden you see not only does
the math become simpler, but you're seeing new symmetries that are true of the data that can't
be seen inside space-time. So what seems to be emerging is that space-time, which we've taken
to be the fundamental reality, looks more and more like a, frankly,
pretty shallow, tired data structure that is a really bad framework. We're sort of stuck with
this data structure in terms of our perceptual, will we perceive the world? And so, what physics
is doing is now realizing we can actually, we don't have to be stuck with either quantum theory or special or general relativity.
We can go beyond them, and we can then project back into those spacetime data structures and get answers much more easily and see deeper symmetries.
So it's in that sense that I'm thinking spacetime is like flat Earth.
It's good for some things.
But if you're trying to build a space program, flat Earth isn't going to do it.
And if you really want to understand the nature – I mean, and space-time is great for certain things.
But if you really want to understand the nature, I think, of consciousness and of reality more deeply, a data structure that falls apart at 10 to the minus 33 centimeters is not a good candidate for
you and i don't want to i certainly wouldn't want to be stuck with that that really shallow
data structure in my thinking in terms of these deeper questions so okay philip um well i suppose
again i i think all of what you've said builds a case, and I couldn't get into the physics of debating that case,
but a case that space-time is not fundamental.
The fact that our models seem to collapse below certain levels suggests they're of limited applicability,
and hence that they don't exist in the fundamental
story of reality i mean you said sean carroll's not sympathetic to space time being doomed well
i think he is if if if by space time being doomed that's just a sort of poetic way of saying it
doesn't exist in our fundamental story of reality and um but yeah i i still think i mean, suppose we think, you know, space-time is
emerging and what we have at the fundamental level is the wave function. I mean, there's going to be,
I presume, a sort of mathematical mapping from the wave function to any state of affairs in in in ordinary quote-unquote three-dimensional reality
and so on that basis we can perhaps make sense of some kind of emergence relationship or
philosophers tend to call this grounding uh scientists tend to talk of emergence but um
yeah i guess i guess i i guess i don't see why this means neurons can't exist unperceived. Why can't we just say they exist unperceived, but their existence, when unperceived, is ultimately rooted in a more fundamental story that is not spatiotemporal for all the reasons you've raised. But yeah,
I suppose that's what I think.
Okay, great. That's a good response. I would say a couple things on the quantum theory aspect of it.
What these high-energy theoretical physicists are saying is that not only is spacetime doomed, but quantum theory is doomed.
So that we're not going to get spacetime emerging from wave functions.
And the new structures that they're finding, like the amplituhedron, the physicists will say, look, there are no Hilbert spaces here.
These new structures, there's no Hilbert space anywhere to be seen.
But we can show you why quantum-like features like unitarity emerge from these deeper structures.
So these deeper structures don't care a bit about Hilbert spaces or quantum theory.
a bit about Hilbert spaces or quantum theory, but you can show how these give rise to unitarity and other quantum-like features at the same time that they give rise to the spacetime
kinds of features.
And another thing about the quantum theory is when you look at the weirdness of quantum
theory, for example, the no-cloning theorem, right? You can't copy quantum bits. And things like superposition and entanglement, sort of the weird aspects of
quantum theory. There are a number of physicists who pointed out that these properties of quantum
theory can really be understood as just arising from lack of information.
Just when you have it, so it's in some sense just due to partial information.
And you can prove that that alone is responsible for these weirdnesses so and that makes sense if space-time is just i like to view it as just a
headset it's just a data structure it's just a data structure that humans use to navigate the
world and we can talk about the evolutionary arguments that i that i have for that but that
data structure is there to simplify, right?
That's the whole point of an interface is to simplify and throw out information.
So all quantum theory,
really all the weirdness of quantum theory
is pointing again to the fact that space-time itself
is a very shallow and information-losing data structure.
And so when we let go of space-time, we're also going to have to let go of quantum theory
because quantum theory is really a symptom of the limitations of spacetime.
I mean, I didn't mean to say this fundamental theory is going to be quantum.
I mean, I was just to use the wave
function as an example i suppose just i mean all what you what what you capture in terms of
uh well it's just a data set it's just a a sort of headset we're wearing it's a way of um i mean the i don't see why we couldn't instead of
that use the other very detailed theories of emergence people have talked about that often
are to do with losing information and and a less fine-grained picture of reality or maybe involving what denick calls real
patterns or um some kind of functional story david albert um and barry lower developed some kind of
functionless story of how we get three-dimensional reality out of more esoteric structures um so
yeah i just don't see why it's almost like you think the only way
of making sense of the non-fundamental is this sort of data structure business. But I mean,
maybe that's one possibility, but there's also other models of emergence. And so it could be,
yeah, neurons are real, but they are emergent from these bizarre structures like
the, I can never pronounce this, what is it, the amplituhedron or something. So their existence
is dependent on those more fundamentally stoic structures. So yeah, I guess I just think of
these as different models of the non-fundamental, and I would be looking for an argument as to whether
to go your way rather than David Albert's or Tim Maudlin or whatever. But yeah.
Fair enough. Fair enough. I would say that so far the other kinds of attempts haven't,
for example, unified gravity with quantum theory, right? So there are promissory notes that haven't, for example, unified gravity with quantum theory, right? So,
there are promissory notes that
haven't yet been fulfilled.
But,
so we can't
point to a success yet in
the emergence.
Hold on, Don.
Sorry, but they're different
fundamental theories. I'm not
advocating a fundamental theory
in physics. I'm not, I'm not advocating a fundamental theory in physics.
I'm just talking about different views of the non-fundamental and the relationship between
the non-fundamental and the fundamental. It seems like you think your conception of the
non-fundamental is always like it's a, it's a data structure. Um, but there, there it is. I'm,
I'm not a physicist or even a philosopher physics i don't i i don't
know what fundamental physics is going to look like but i i guess i'm not seeing why we can't
whatever it looks like even if it's the uh ampedlehedrons that i can ever pronounce
uh or whatever um i should have rehearsed this shouldn't i learn how to pronounce that
um it's basically like amplitude just forget the d to and then just say hedrons amplitohedrons oh thank you
what now why didn't i ask you that before we went live anyway everyone thinks i'm an idiot now yeah
but those people don't have any neurons so don't worry about it so yeah whatever fundamental physics
is whatever is whatever kind of funny structures are at the bottom of that, I don't see why we can't make sense of space-time as emergent from those non-spatio-temporal structures.
We can, in the same way that we can get some kind of relationship between, for example, Einstein and quantum theory versus Newton.
And we can show that Newton is a special case of Einstein.
If you let the speed of light go to infinity,
or if you let Planck's constant, in the case of quantum theory,
if you let Planck's constant go to zero,
then you can get versions of Newton as special cases of the deeper theory.
And that's the sense in which I'm thinking about these structures beyond space-time,
is that we'll find that space time emerges as a special case of a much much deeper so i mean for example
we can still i'm happy with all that i'm happy with every everything you just said i'm happy
but but then but then no no but then you go okay so it's data structures and it's the headset we're
wearing and they don't exist when they're not perceived. I think that's a sort of non-sequitur. That's a
further step from everything you just said. Sure. That's another step in the sense of
going with the local realism being false, right? There I'm saying, I mean, the Nobel Prize was
just given last December for local realism being false. And so I believe the physics,
local realism is false, end of story believe the physics. Local realism is false.
End of story.
That's the way.
Now, there are some physicists who will disagree.
There's some who will say there's super determinism as a way out.
So look, we can keep local realism if we assume that there's super determinism or something like that.
So there are issues about this, but
there's something I think that we
might have in common here that I'd like to push
on, and that is
the physicists
who are looking for structures beyond
spacetime are right now just finding geometric
objects. The amplituhedron is
not a polytube, but it's a geometric
structure.
And decorator permutations are combinatorial mathematical structures.
But there's no dynamics.
And ultimately, we're going to have to say, when we step outside of spacetime, physics likes dynamics.
And we're going to be talking about dynamical entities beyond spacetime, not inside spacetime, not curled up inside spacetime. Dynamical entities outside space-time, not inside space-time, not curled up inside space-time,
dynamical entities outside of space-time. Now, here's the perfect place for you and me
to say, hey, well, what about consciousness, right? What about conscious entities entirely
outside of space-time? And that's, see, that's where I'm working with my own theories and saying,
okay, let's just go with this.
The Nobel Prize was correct.
Local realism is false.
Space-time is not fundamental, and we need to find dynamical entities entirely outside of space-time.
They will project into space-time, of course, just like Newton is a projection of Einstein and quantum theory.
But it will be a special case of
some deeper structure. So why not go after a theory of consciousness, the dynamics of consciousness
that's not tied to space-time physics, but has the important constraint that whatever theory
of consciousness we come up with outside of space-time, whatever dynamics, we must, with mathematical precision,
show precisely how space-time arises as a special projection,
and all the dynamics of particles and all the dynamical laws of physics inside space-time
emerges as a very, very special case of a far more general dynamical system of consciousness.
And that would turn the whole tables around.
Instead of saying, of course we know that objects in space-time are real and the laws, and we're trying to fit consciousness into that.
To say, no, no, no, no.
That is the relatively trivial thing.
The deeper thing is consciousness itself.
the relatively trivial thing. The deeper thing is consciousness itself. We can get a mathematical theory of consciousness qua consciousness and show a projection in which space-time emerges
as a fairly trivial example of a far richer dynamics of consciousness. Now, of course,
we have to do it, right? We have to actually give the precise mathematical laws and get the precise
predictions. But if we could do that, that would change the whole thing around.
Consciousness would not then be a second, you know, second fiddle to things in space and time or just an equal fiddle.
It would be, in fact, the real story and space-time itself would be a projection of this much
deeper story.
I would think you would like that kind of story.
Yeah, yeah. i would think you would like that kind of story yeah yeah well like i suppose we're coming back
to this the sense in which we the point of agreement between us that there's a
consciousness that at the fundamental level maybe we have slightly different stories
to fit this in um what do you think should we move on to some of the other questions or should
we continue on yeah back and forth this so i would prefer that we not stick to the physics but instead stick to the philosophy philip if you don't mind don i have
some quick objections just from a physics point of view because i just can't let them go so number
one when someone says the physicists are finding these phenomenon it's not the physicists there
there are maybe 30 of those physicists of the
30,000 that exist that follow NEMA's program. It's a minority. Maybe 25 people do. And then
number two is that the amplituhedron doesn't capture non-perturbative effects. So confinement
isn't there. And almost all of the world is non-perturbative. We don't know how much is
perturbative. And number three is that, okay, just because something simplifies
calculations, even if drastically, it doesn't imply an ontological reality to the ingredients
that go into the simplification. So for instance, there are two billiard balls that bounce off one
another. We can model that with trillions and trillions and trillions of calculations and pages
that take into account all the sub components and substances inside this
billiard ball and the paint and the reflections or we can just take their center of masses and
and have them bounce off one another that doesn't mean the center of mass is more real than all the
components that make it up and now number four is that the nobel prize was given because of
local realism or disproving realism or local realism.
However, this is just something that's said in the popular press. And when you interview the
people who have won the Nobel Prize, they're not anti-realists. In fact, they'll say that
Bell's theorem doesn't assume realism because Bell's theorem is a mathematical theorem,
any more so than stokes
theorem assumes reality quote-unquote or the triangle equality assumes reality like there's
no axiom of reality okay now the next one and apologies if i'm going on for too long but the
the positive geometry of nema assumes not only supersymmetry which is dubious but extended supersymmetry so a perverse form of
an n equals four if i'm not mistaken and furthermore you mentioned that the theories don't incorporate
gravity well neither does nemas okay lastly if we're to take it to be the case that if we are
to probe the plank length then we'd create a black hole. Well, one, what's wrong with creating a
black hole? Black holes exist. Number two, if that was to mean that somehow the plank length doesn't
exist, well, that's an operationalist view on reality in the same way that we can say the
inside of a black hole doesn't exist because we can't observe it. There are many other views on
what existence is other than operationalism. So I'm done. Those
are just some quick objections. Don, I'd love to hear your thoughts. I think that those are all
very, very good points. So for example, the amplituhedron assumes n equals four super Yang
mills. So it's supersymmetry. It's only for massless. That particular one is only for massless particles. And you're right, it doesn't extend gravity.
So this is fairly new work.
There's some papers in the last couple of years where NEMA has gone to all masses and spins.
So it's not just – but I think it still involves supersymmetric ideas, and that may end up being false.
We'll have to see.
What's interesting, though, is this has only been at
it for a decade, you know, literally going after this stuff, structures beyond space-time,
and we're finding interesting stuff. And it's, I think, very encouraging. Of course,
there's limitations to what we found, but it's really quite encouraging. And I agree as well that there are physicists who think that the experiments that
got the Nobel Prize don't count against local realism. Some think that it shows that we're
in a world of super determinism. So, all of your points are well taken. It's a matter of,
yeah, the final answer's not in, but I'm suggesting that there's this interesting direction
that is coming out of the new physics.
And ultimately, physics is going to look for some dynamics
of entities beyond space-time.
And that is interesting.
When we talk about dynamics of entities outside of space-time,
what kinds of entities are those?
What are we going to put there as the entities? That is, so that's what I'm, that's ultimately
what I'm exploring here is what happens if we start with entities that we take just to
be consciousness and we get a precise mathematics and we can show that we can boot up all of space-time and quantum theory from that.
It wouldn't prove that this is the right framework, but it sure is intriguing, right?
As a scientist, it would be very, very intriguing.
And it would raise deep philosophical issues.
I mean, what kinds of entities beyond space-time are we talking about here?
These are no longer physical entities. They're not in space-time we'll be talking about here. These are no longer
physical entities. They're not in space-time. What are they? So, we're going to have to
think. Ultimately, if we find a physics beyond space-time, and it's a dynamical system, we're
going to have to have a theory about what those entities are like. What are they about?
And why is there this dynamics going on?
Of course, it'll be open to us to give a non-conscious approach, of course.
Philip, I have a question. When Don was saying, look, the neurons don't exist,
which I'm just going to pick up this pen and say this pen doesn't exist prior to looking at it,
sorry, prior to observation, and then you were saying, no, no, it can exist,
but at the same time, this is made out of consciousness.
Can you not reconcile those two views by saying the pen is observing itself because the pen is made up of subjective experiences?
Like, is there a way to make the objective from the subjective?
Well, I wouldn't say that.
I wouldn't quite put it that way that the pen is observing it. Well, I mean, maybe I could talk a little bit more about the inspiration for the contemporary panpsychist resurgence, which very much draws on crucial work from the 1920s by Bertrand Russell.
Sorry to interrupt, it would also be helpful if you were to distinguish it from idealism, panpsychism.
Yeah, yeah, sure, sure. Let me do that.
So it's very much the somewhat rediscovery of this crucial work from Russell, particularly in the analysis of matter,
that has made panpsychism in the last decade go from something that was laughed at insofar as it was thought of at all
to being a serious academic option that's
taught to our undergraduates, published on and so on. So right, so what I think this connects a lot
to what Don was saying as well. So what Russell was thinking very hard about in the 1920s
was the fact that our fundamental science, physics is just purely mathematical, right? Something we kind of take for granted. And of
course, that's very useful if you're a working physicist, you get very precise predictions and
so on. But Russell's thinking, what does it mean as a philosopher interested in the ultimate nature
of reality that our basic science is just equations? And what Russell concluded is that what it means is that our
basic science isn't really telling us that much about what fundamental reality is. It's merely
describing its mathematical structure. And so as far as physics is concerned,
fundamental reality could turn out to be anything. As long as it has the right mathematical structure,
you're going to get physics out of that. That's all physics cares about.
So the contemporary Bertrand Russell-inspired panpsychists exploit this, and the idea is that
what we have at the fundamental level of reality are very simple conscious entities,
networks of simple conscious entities interacting in very
simple, predictable ways. Through their interactions, they realize certain patterns,
certain mathematical structures. And then the idea is those mathematical structures
just are what we call physics. So we sort of get physics out of underlying facts about consciousness. So I don't
think you can get consciousness out of physics, but I think you can get physics out of consciousness.
I think we know that can be done. I think we should think of Russell as the Darwin of consciousness.
I think he essentially solved all the mysteries here. But what this ends up as, and this is where I think it maybe contrasts with what I think of as Don's idealism is that there's a kind of identity between consciousness and physical reality. I, as I sometimes put it, matter is what consciousness does. Um, really there's just consciousness stuff, but physics is the mathematical structure of that consciousness stuff.
As Stephen Hawking said on the last page of A Brief History of Time,
physics doesn't tell us what breathes fire into the equations and makes a universe for them to
describe. For the Rosilian panpsychist, it's consciousness that breathes fire into the equations so when so so so i just
connecting it to what don was saying i mean don seems to have this idea that like
this physics he's attracted to or this new physics makes it more problematic um to you know we need
to look elsewhere than space time we need to look for new entities but from my
perspective my birch and russ birch and russell inspired perspective physics has never told us
ever what reality is like it's just a bunch of maths it's it's not unless you go for max
tegmark's view and think you know the universe is made up of maths then physics just is not in
the business of telling us what has never been in the business.
So it doesn't matter whether, you know, the amplituhedron ends up being the right stuff,
or whether we get Bohmian spacetime. It's just maths, and we'll always need something to fill
out that mathematical structure, something to breathe fire into the equations. And for the panpsychist, well, the most parsimonious answer
is consciousness because we know consciousness exists. I think there are good reasons to think
if you put just mathematical structure at the fundamental level, you're not going to be able
to get consciousness out of that. But we know it can be done the other way around, and so that seems to me the more plausible view. So yeah, that's kind of how I think about things. Does that make sense?
say, why just the laws of physics? Why not the consciousness? Why should we restrict our imagination to say that the laws of physics that we happen to know are all that consciousness
has done? Why not say that there are an infinite number of other, quote-unquote, physics that
consciousness chooses to play with. This is
just one. Space-time physics is one perhaps more trivial kind of physics that consciousness
has chosen to make. Why should we put ourselves in a conceptual straitjacket and only
work with the physics that we've seen. In the amplituhedron, it is parameterized by three
integers, n, k, and m. And m is basically an integer that dials up the different universes
that you might choose. So with the amplituhedron, you can have our four-dimensional space-time as
the projection of this deeper structure, but you can also have an eight-dimensional spacetime. You can have spacetimes of 20, 30. In other words,
you can already with the new physics that they're finding outside of spacetime, you
can choose which kind of spacetime universe you want to create. And our 4D one is just
one of an infinite number of possibilities. And so already the physics in just the first decade of stepping outside of
space-time is saying, whoa, the space-time projection of this deeper physics is clearly
just one of an infinite number of projections. I'm saying, okay, let's go with what the math is
saying. Consciousness is not in the space-time straitjacket. It's free to have an infinite number of completely
different kinds of physics with different kinds of laws. And for us to be wedded to the space-time
one is to limit our imagination about what consciousness can really do and what it really is.
I suppose I'm very, I mean, very strictly an empiricist on this point. People might find that surprising,
given my philosophical views. But as I say, for the panpsychist, there's a kind of identity between... So the panpsychist will say, you know, sometimes people say to me, you know,
well, what's the kind of mathematics of your theory? And my answer is, ask a physicist,
right? So for the Bertrand Russell style panpsychist, it's the job of physics to identify what Russell called the causal skeleton of reality. The job of physics is to identify the mathematical structure of reality, the dynamics, and then our philosophical interpretation of that is that that mathematical structure is filled out by consciousness, because I think it's the best solution to the mind-body problem.
But it's just a question for physics, or more broadly, an empirical question.
So, I mean, you've talked about the dynamics of consciousness and the
dynamics of physical reality. For me, they're just the same thing, right? And so, okay, these infinite
causal structures of consciousness, maybe they're possible, but I'm going to want empirical reason
to think they're actual. I'm going to look for empirical grounds from physics to tell me what
the dynamics of consciousness are, which for me is just equivalent to the dynamics of physical reality, the reality physicists are trying to articulate.
Of course, I'm on the same page.
Whatever theories we propose about dynamics of consciousness outside of space-time, and if I propose all these other kinds of universes, quote-unquote physical universes, then I would want to try to find some kind of empirical tests.
Absolutely.
So I agree with you on that.
It's just that I don't think that we should a priori rule out the possibility that there are many, many more ways that consciousness can give rise to quote-unquote physics than the one that we happen to know.
And as we start to think out of that box,
we may be able to find clean empirical tests of that hypothesis.
Yeah.
I'm finding it difficult to see where you disagree.
So is it, Philip, that, because it sounds like you all agree at your fundament
that consciousness is at the fundament. But then, Philip, you believe Don is making a jump from there to something speculative and doing so with confidence? Or is it not that?
It's just that I suppose I'm happy to say this pen exists when we're not observing it.
And I would say all the things about it a normal physicalist materialist would say,
you know, there's light bouncing off it, hitting our eyes.
And yeah, I'm not...
This talk of it's a data structure, that it's a headset we were um i'm not fully seeing the
motivation i mean maybe we should maybe we should talk about the the evolution stuff as well briefly
or um which i guess is the is the other point where we disagree maybe i'll just say one thing
in regard to just because of what you said just brought up another way that i might get at this
drink some wine and that is to say that that if you think of consciousness as fundamental and that I'm having conscious experiences.
So, I'm having experience as of a pen, right?
You held up a pen.
And I don't, if I take consciousness to be fundamental, I can say I definitely know that I have the conscious experience as of a pen.
Now, someone might come along and say, but you know, in addition to your experience, there really is.
There is a pen.
And not just your experience of a pen, there is a pen.
And I say, well, I don't know what the evidence is for that.
I don't really need it.
I can completely do my physics without any assumption that there's anything but the experiences.
And I can write down the equations.
So, I don't see why I need this extra ontological baggage of the real pen.
And, you know, there is a pen when I pound the table.
There really is a pen.
Well, I have an experience and that's all I really need. So, why do I need the real pen, and there is a pen, and I pound the table, there really is a pen. Well, I have an experience, and that's all I really need.
So why do I need the real pen?
Why don't I just say local realism is false?
There is no real pen, but there is a real experience, and that's all I really need.
And as Einstein put it, the laws of physics just basically are there to show us how we can predict new experiences from old experiences.
laws of physics just basically are there to show us how we can predict new experiences from old experiences yeah well i suppose look we want we want a theory that fits together the um
the story we're getting from physics and the reality of consciousness i suppose they're the
two data points for me but i mean maybe we could agree on the fundamental story. I suppose I just think
a lot of philosophers and philosophers of physics have come up with detailed and rigorous theories
of emergence where we can make sense of the pen, not as a sort of extra thing in the ontology,
just something, maybe just to take Dennett's view that it's a sort of a real pattern or something in
the more fundamental. What is a real pattern in Dennett's view?
So we've got the, you know, you could know all of physical reality at the level of fundamental
physics, all that detail. But that's not very useful for many practical purposes for many. And I mean, maybe this connects with what you were saying, Kurt, about sometimes it's not the fundamental thing that gives you the more information with less axioms or what have you. reality. Dennett talks about the intentional stance when you treat something as an agent with
thoughts and experiences, or the design stance when you treat something as a designed object.
They can be more useful structures for prediction rather than trying to work out from fundamental
physics when your alarm clock's going to go off or
whatever. But maybe it would help to connect to the evolution stuff. Should we go there now?
Yeah, please. And then also, you mentioned the word useful here. And I imagine, I don't want
to speak for Don, but that Don would agree that, sure, it's useful, but useful is a different
statement than, is it true or does it exist? I don't't know i don't want to put words in your mouth don sorry no that those are good yeah yeah so then it starts it starts to get tricky to see to see
see where the difference is perhaps but um yeah anyway so so this is uh i guess coming to to
don's other argument and we've been back and forth with this a little bit on my mind chat podcast um
so so don's evolutionary argument that um get just very roughly done can
articulate it for himself but the given that our senses are are evolved for fitness rather than
truth we shouldn't trust them to tell us that in fact i think don has said there's zero chance
they're telling us the truth about reality well i, I'm still a bit hung up with an objection.
It's not my objection raised by a philosopher. Jeffrey Bagwell is actually published in quite
prestigious philosophy journal, Synthes, a paper called, what's it called now? Debunking Interface
Theory. So what Bagwell presses on Don is that there's sort of something self-defeating
about his argument, right? Because if our senses have evolved for fitness rather than truth,
so we can't trust them, how do we know we evolved, right? We only know we've evolved because we can
use our senses, you know, look at fossils and things. So this is something self-defeating
about this argument. And yeah'm i'm i mean i'm
not totally persuaded by this but i'm still um a little bit uh taken by this objection gone down
what do you reckon yeah so yeah i've read bagel's paper and i can summarize his objection myself
it it says that um don's using the mathematics of evolutionary game theory
to show that fundamental ideas in Darwin's theory, namely that there are physical organisms
competing for physical resources in a physical space and time. He's using evolutionary game
theory, which is supposed to model Darwin's theory, to actually show that
fundamental ideas in Darwin's theory aren't correct. So now, the argument goes, so now
either the mathematics of evolutionary game theory is a faithful
model of Darwin's ideas, or it's not. If it's not, then Hoffman shouldn't use it to try to
disprove things about Darwin's theory. And if it is a faithful model, it would never give you any
reason to dispute the fundamental things that Darwin's theory is assumed, physical objects in space-time. In either case, Don's in an unfortunate dialectical situation, right?
So, now, my reply is quite simple.
This fundamentally misunderstands the nature of scientific theories and what they do.
Fundamental misunderstanding.
Let's go to Einstein's theory of space-time.
Gravity. misunderstanding. Let's go to Einstein's theory of space-time, gravity. So, Einstein's idea was that gravity is, well, his big idea was that if I'm standing on a scale in an elevator,
I'm weighing myself, and all of a sudden the cable is cut, and I'm in free fall, I would go to zero,
right away zero in space-time. And it took him several years, I would go to zero, right away zero, in space-time.
And it took him several years,
better part of a decade,
to turn that idea into mathematics.
But he finally, so his idea about,
so he's thinking space-time is real, it's fundamental.
And he writes down these mathematical equations.
Now, later on, we find out from his equations, and also from another equation he wrote down, E equals H nu, when you put those two together, you find out that his idea of spacetime,
first, number one, it has a beautiful scope to the theory. It's incredible, the scope of Einstein's
general theory of relativity. It's one of the marvels of all time. But also the mathematics tells us the limits of that theory.
Einstein's theory of space-time is great until you get to 10 to the minus 33 centimeters.
And then his own mathematics tells you that those concepts are no longer coherent.
So what happens is when we take a mathematical theory in science,
in every single case, you will get not only the scope,
but also the limits of the fundamental concepts that were mathematized. So, what I'm doing is not
some kind of ad hoc weird thing. This is the way science has to work. No theory is the theory of
everything in science. Every theory makes certain assumptions. And you
then make those assumptions precise with mathematics. And then if you've done it right,
you find the scope, the explanatory scope of those assumptions, and you find the explanatory limits of
those assumptions. And that's what makes science much better than non-mathematical ideas. With non-mathematical statements,
it's hard to know where your theory stops. What are the limits of your theory?
In science, with mathematics, we can say Einstein's ideas are great. At 10 to the minus 32 centimeters, they're great. At 10 to the minus 33 centimeters, nope, they're not. There's the
scope and the limits. And so, Bagwell's argument,
if taken seriously, would be an argument against any of basically the way science actually
progresses, where we take, so here's what we do in science. We take our ideas, our assumptions,
we mathematize them, we find the scope, and we then look for the limits. And as soon as we find
the limits, we go, hooray.
Now let's find a deeper set of assumptions and new mathematics.
And this is the way we pull ourselves up by the bootstraps.
So Bagwell has sort of taken as a problem what is, in fact, the central strength of science.
Yeah, yeah.
So two points on that.
I'm not entirely convinced by that response. I mean, one thing is, yes, I totally agree with what you've just said about scientific progress.
I share that sort of, you know, the standard view and philosophy of science is that, in physics at least, it's important to distinguish, you know, different sciences.
in physics, we discover that the old theory only works in a certain domain of applicability,
and then maybe it breaks down, or we look to a broader theory. So maybe you gave a great example of general relativity, or maybe Newton's law of gravity works in a certain domain but not not outside of it um but bagwell's this critique
is not is not qualified in that way it's not it's not saying your argument fails in a certain
domain of applicability it's not it's not it's not qualified in that way it's just saying it fails itself yeah it's saying the the argument cannot
succeed because it's self-defeating because the argument relies on the assumption that we evolved
but it also tells us that we we wouldn't be able to know that we evolved um So itself, and it's not saying that it's not qualified in the way we could
raise this problem with general relativity. Oh, it doesn't work in this domain of inquiry,
our domain of applicability. That's not what it's saying. It's just saying it doesn't work, period.
Again, the way I think about it is that what I'm doing is I'm saying,
let's assume for sake of argument
Darwin's theory of evolution, financial selection,
just like I did with Einstein.
Let's assume for sake of argument
Einstein's theory of gravity.
If we assume that that's true,
then we get the Einstein field equations.
And then we can ask the question,
assuming that Einstein is right,
we get these field equations,
then we can ask,
so,
are there any,
Einstein assumed that space-time is fundamental.
Can we use his mathematics
to confirm his point of view?
We find out,
well,
it's not.
It's not fundamental.
It stops at 10 to the minus 33 centimeters. We find out, well, it's not. It's not fundamental. It stops at 10 to the minus
33 centimeters. So, now, are we being self-refuting by saying, let's assume with Einstein that
spacetime is fundamental. We get the field equations. Now, let's look at those equations
and say, now, what do those equations say about spacetime? Well, they say it falls apart at 10
to the minus 33 centimeters. So, now I'm using the
same logic with evolution. I'm saying, okay, we have Darwin's theory of evolution. It talks about
organisms in space-time competing for resources. And now we have, you know, John Maynard Smith has
made evolutionary game theory. He's turned Darwin's ideas into mathematics. So, now we can
say, okay, we have this really good mathematical model.
We can now ask, what are the scope and limits of the fundamental ideas? For example, should we
believe that our perceptions are telling us the truth about objective reality or not? Well, it
turns out we can answer that question using evolutionary game theory, for better or for
worse. We may not like the answer, but the answer is that the probability is precisely zero, that any sensory system has ever been shaped to see any true
structures of objective reality. That's an implication of Maynard Smith's Mathematization
of Darwin. So that means that when I see physical objects in space-time, what I'm seeing almost
surely is not the truth. And that means that the assumption that objects in space-time are the fundamental reality is almost surely not the truth on Darwin's own theory.
Just as with Einstein's case, we start with Einstein assuming that space-time is fundamental, and then we use his own mathematics to say it can't be, because it falls apart at 10 to the minus 33 centimeters.
Same logic.
But I'm pointing out
again that this happens
not just in these two cases,
this happens in every
good, precise,
scientific theory. We will always find
the limits of those concepts.
When we have a set of
concepts, they will always have a limit, and we're trying to find in science what the limits of those concepts. When we have a set of concepts, they will always have a limit,
and we're trying to find in science what the limits of those concepts are.
But what is the analogue in your argument of domain of applicability,
if that's the right terminology? You're identifying this limitation with Einstein's
theory that it breaks down in a certain domain, but it still works in a certain domain,
but it breaks down in this other domain. But this objection, as I say, there's nothing analogous to
that. It's just saying, if your argument works, we don't know we evolved. So your argument doesn't
work. So there's no analog of the domain of applicability. I mean, maybe the objection
fails for reasons I haven't thought of yet, but if the objection works, it doesn't say
your argument, we can still use evolution in this limited domain. It just says the argument
doesn't work. What's the analogue of domain of applicability here?
Well, in Einstein's case, the fact comes out that space-time isn't fundamental.
So Darwin's theory is not fundamental, but neither is Einstein's theory is fundamental.
What we can do then is ask, is there a deeper theory?
But it still works in a limited domain of applicability.
Oh, absolutely.
Yeah, what's the analog of the debate about applicability in this evolutionary argument?
Oh, for all practical purposes, for example, my book, The Case Against Reality, I spend half of the book exploring the power of Darwin's theory.
I use it with companies to help them sell products and make jeans that make you look better and so forth.
I use Darwin's theory in great, great detail to actually do practical things. I think
that it's a wonderful theory inside spacetime, just like Einstein's theory is a wonderful theory
inside spacetime. Within the framework of spacetime, Darwin's theory works wonderfully,
and so does Einstein. But this argument isn't saying it's self-defeating unless you're
But this argument isn't saying it's self-defeating unless you're in the domain of space-time or something.
It's saying it's self-defeating.
It doesn't, the argument doesn't work.
Because if the argument works, we don't know we evolved.
So the argument doesn't work if it works.
I mean, yeah, it just, it means the whole thing just, it means the argument doesn't work.
Period.
I don't know.
I can't. Yeah. I don't know. I can't, uh, yeah, I don't know. I'm repeating myself. Well, can I, in case I'm repeating myself, can I raise it like a slightly
different way of thinking about it? Yeah. You know, I mean, I, I mean, natural selection is
a very different scientific theory to theories in physics. And I mean, I don't agree with Richard Dawkins on a lot
of things, but I like him on evolution. And I agree with Dawkins that we need natural selection
to explain the apparent design, right? And I know it's slightly complicated, Don, because you don't
necessarily believe in the physical world, but you believe in our conscious minds. And I think
our conscious minds exhibit apparent
design, you know, the way their functioning is so structured and coherent and logical,
and we have the capacity to reason. There needs an explanation of where that apparent design
comes from. Natural selection provides it. So I think we need the theory of evolution by natural selection to be true, to be true. Whereas, you know, if you seem to have an argument that we can't know it to be... Okay, so I can say what the next step is in my own way of thinking about things.
And then you'll see why I'm still maintaining that this is not a problem.
So we have this Markovian dynamics of conscious agents outside of space-time.
And it turns out when you look at this Markovian dynamics,
the entropy in the dynamics does not need to increase. It's easier for us to write
down dynamical system of conscious agents in which the entropy is not increasing. So there's no arrow
of time in terms of an entropic arrow of time in these dynamics. But it's a theorem, a very simple
theorem, that if you take a projection of this dynamical system that loses information, say using conditional
probability. So you get a new dynamical system, which is a projection of the deeper dynamical
system that has no arrow of time. The new projected system will necessarily have an arrow of time.
The entropy will increase because of the loss of information. So the idea is then that the arrow of time that you experience in this projected dynamics
is not an insight into the true nature of the deeper dynamics it's entirely an artifact of
the projection process now now to the evolution what is the fundamental limited resource in
evolution it's time if you don't get food in time, you die. If you don't mate in time,
you don't reproduce. If you don't get water in time, you die. What I'm saying is, if we can have
a dynamical system of consciousness outside of space-time that has no arrow of time,
we take a projection by a conditional probability, and we get a new dynamical system inside space-time in which there is an arrow of time and which now there appears to be limited resources and organisms fighting in time and surviving, reproducing in time.
And it turns out that all of that is an artifact of loss of information and projection from a deeper dynamical system
in which there is no arrow of time. So what we would get then is, and this is how science works,
I would find a new framework in which the arrow of time doesn't exist. There are no limited
resources. There is no competition. But when you take a projection of it, you get Darwin's theory
of evolution of a natural selection precisely, you get evolutionary game theory precisely in that special domain of projection.
So then we would have, so then we would explain why Darwin's theory was so successful in
its domain and why we could use Darwin's theory itself to predict that it would not
be ultimately successful because it had limited concepts.
So this is again, I'm trying to show how science works.
So ultimately, we take our theories.
Every theory will have its assumptions.
They will, they necessarily, there is, I make a bold statement.
There is no scientific theory that will ever be published that does not have a limit.
And its own mathematics better tell you the limit
or it's not a good theory. That's the way science works. And when you do that, then you'll get a
deeper theory and explain why that new, for example, why evolution seems to be so powerful
in this domain and where the theory comes from and how it's an artifact of a deeper theory.
So now you seem to be saying that, okay, natural selection is true, but it's not fundamental.
But your argument from Fitness Beats Truth is not an argument that evolution is not part
of the fundamental story, or it's only in the domain of space-time.
It's saying, given that our senses evolved,
we can't trust them to tell us about reality.
But if we can't trust them to tell us about reality,
we don't know we evolved, period.
We don't know we evolved.
It's not just we don't know evolution is you know is true in some deep fundamental sense and there really is space and time out there no if your argument works we
do not know we evolved period uh but if we don't know we evolved then a the argument doesn't work
so it's self-defeating but also we can't explain the apparent design in our conscious minds.
I think evolution does...
Yeah, so that's the problem.
I think you seem to be interpreting your own argument
in a way that doesn't seem to be accurate,
because you seem to be interpreting the argument to say,
like, we didn't evolve
in such a way that space and time...
Yeah, I'm repeating myself, so I'll stop.
Can I see if I understand it correctly, and then you all can correct?
Sure.
So Einstein's theory of gravity doesn't say anything about the Planck length
or not being able to go to it.
Only if you combine Einstein's theory of gravity doesn't say anything about the Planck length or not being able to go to it. Only if you combine Einstein's with quantum mechanics do you get this limit of...
Like, a general relativity is consistent.
With the theory of the photoelectric effect, if you put in E equals h nu, then you get it.
Yeah, though that's not GR. That's GR in combination with quantum mechanics.
Right, right.
Okay.
You do get Black-Hole's out of GR, though.
Sure, sure, sure.
Right, right. Okay. You do get black holes out of GR though. Sure, sure, sure. So the point is that, look, in a theory like, let's say, GR, or whatever,
whichever theory, it would say, you can't exit through all of these doors. There are 300 doors,
maybe there are 10 of them which you can't exit. So it's showing some limits. Those are the
scientific theories that point out their own limits. But, Philip, it sounds like you're saying Don's theory is akin to
A implies B implies not A.
Which is different.
Yeah, which is not saying
the theory doesn't work.
Like, inherently contradictory as a whole.
So is that what you're saying?
So it's different than pointing out that there's some doors we can't
go through. Exactly.
That's a good way of putting it.
Okay, so Don, then your response to that.
So I reply, every scientific theory is not the truth. There is no scientific theory which is the truth. Every scientific theory says, grant me these assumptions, I will then explain this range of phenomena.
But scientific theories cannot be the truth.
They can only be projections of the truth.
And so the question is, we take our assumptions of our theories, we find out the scope of that projection and the limits of that projection.
But there's no such thing as, so when I say I like evolution by natural selection, I wrote half of my book on it.
It's a wonderful projection and it's a theory, and it's not deeply true. And Einstein's theory of spacetime is a wonderful theory,
and it's not deeply true. We're going to let go of spacetime altogether. We will find new pyramids. And this is the way science, so I'm saying this is the way, so there is no theory
of everything. My big point here is there is no theory of everything.
There cannot be.
And therefore, every theory will ultimately be false.
It can be a good projection of whatever the truth is.
It can be a useful projection, but it's not the truth.
And so all we can do is say, why does evolution work?
Well, it's a good projection. And I love, I mean, inside space-time, there is no better theory about our origins and so forth. But as soon as we step outside of space-time, then all of a sudden, we don't even need the notion of limited resources.
But we can see how limited resources arises as an artifact of projection.
so so so i'm i'm saying that if if we want to say that i've caught myself in a terrible you know self-contradiction this is what's going to happen with every single scientific theory
and in the same way that i'm doing it with evolution it has to because i mean you sort of
it's like the it's it's true or it's deeply true. I think that gets a precise meaning in terms of these theories in physics where we can say, well, it's true in a domain of applicability, but it's not true per se across the board.
see how we carry that over to natural sex. In what sense is it true, but not true? I think it needs to be true. But yeah. And again, the argument is not just that it's not true
in a certain domain of inquiry.
Okay, how about this? Did we evolve yes or or no and then i want to hear both of your
answers to that okay great i would say yes yeah i mean i i take the the standard scientific view
of this yeah don and i would say that um when we look at reality through a particular space-time headset, it looks like we evolved. But the evolution
framework takes time as a fundamental entity. I don't think time is a fundamental entity.
I think time is an artifact. It takes objects in space-time as fundamental.
It takes space-time as fundamental. I think space-time doesn't even work beyond 10 to the
minus 33 centimeters. Speaking of Daniel Dennett, he said that the fundamental unit of natural
selection is one that undergoes replication, variation, and selection. Now, this selection
mechanism can be abstract. It doesn't just have to be with respect to time. mechanism can be abstract it doesn't just
have to be with respect to time it can be any resource so given that does evolution or natural
selection indeed reference time or would you say yeah there's an implicit time parameter because
of steps well when you go more abstract and evolutionary game through you still have a time
parameter right you have for example the success game theory, you still have a time parameter, right? You have, for example, the success of generations gives you essentially a time parameter.
I see.
So I'm saying that this is a ubiquitous feature about how science works.
Each theory will have its own set of concepts, like organisms competing in time for resources and dying and having reproduction. And it will have
its domain of applicability. And by the way, most theories we come up with have no domain of
applicability. They're just useless. We have these rare theories that really are wonderful in a
domain, like evolution of a natural selection is beautiful in this domain, but it's not deeply true. I think
that time isn't deeply true. And so, the foundational concept of evolution in time
is fundamentally flawed. What's beautiful about the theory of evolution is that its own mathematics
allows you to predict its own limits. And that's not self-contradiction, that is the glory of scientific
theories, that the theories predict their demise.
I've got a slightly different way of trying to make the point. Okay, so you don't
think evolution is true in some deep sense, but you think it's true in some more lightweight
sense in some domain of applicability.
Okay, and I'm struggling to articulate that difference.
But just take that for granted.
How do you know we evolved in that more lightweight sense?
How do you know?
Agreeing we're talking about that more lightweight sense,
how do you know we evolved?
Oh, well, I would say that from this deeper point of view,
we know that we didn't.
But it's a useful framework within space-time.
It's a very useful framework to think about it as evolution.
It's true in some sense, right?
It's true in this projection or whatever.
Well, it's like if I'm playing Grand Theft Auto in virtual reality.
Oh, great point.
Trailer just got dropped for Grand Theft Auto 6. Oh, my gosh.
Fantastic. Right, gosh. Fantastic.
Right, right. So if I say there's some supercomputer I'm interacting with, and all I see is Grand Theft Auto, right? And so I'm racing in my car.
So I can say I'm racing in a red Ferrari, and my car can go faster than your green Mustang and so forth. And those may be true statements in the game, but ultimately they're only true of the game. And if I say,
but I'm going to go now to a bigger framework, I'm going to look at outside of the Grand Theft Auto world. What is that? Well, some supercomputer. Well, now, is it really true that there's a red
Ferrari and a green Mustang? Well, no, if you actually look inside the supercomputer,
you won't find anything like red Ferraris or green Mustangs anywhere inside there. You'll find bits
and so forth. But within the context of the headset, sure, that's the best theory and that's
what you should do. But a good theory of Grand Theft Auto would actually tell you, you know,
there's more to life than Grand Theft Auto. It won't tell you that there's a supercomputer, but it will tell you that Grand Theft Auto can't
be the whole story. And that's all I'm doing with evolution. It's not the whole story.
I'm trying to focus on that, that from within the Grand Theft Auto world, from within the headset,
the sense, there's got to be some sense in which the creationist is wrong right that the earth is
four thousand years old that we didn't evolve by natural selection there's some sense in which the
creationist is wrong okay it's not a deep sense my question is how do you know how do we know that
the creationist is wrong and the darwinian is right in that in that head headset relative context
and surely you've got to say,
well, we used our senses.
We used our senses to find out
that the creationist is wrong.
I don't think you can say that
if your argument works,
because if your argument works,
our senses evolve for truth,
not fitness, not truth.
We don't know.
We don't know if the creationist
is right or wrong.
This is the key point.
We don't need to believe any of our theories, right?
I'm a scientist.
I create theories and I evaluate theories.
So all I do is I take the theories and I'm not stuck inside my theories.
I'm the one that creates them and evaluates them.
I just look at evolution of a natural selection and say, here's the mathematics.
The mathematics entails the probability of zero that I have any true perceptions. That's what
that theory says. Now, what I believe about my senses is something different. I may still say,
I don't believe that implication of evolution. It's nevertheless an implication of evolution.
So, I can say that I love evolution. It has all this power.
But my senses are not limited.
For example, I might say that.
But the mathematics of evolutionary game theory says that they are limited.
Aha!
That's what that theory entails.
Maybe I want to say that there's a point where I disagree with evolutionary theory.
I love it for all this other stuff. But on the other hand, I may say, you know, maybe it's when it says we shouldn't take our perceptions literally.
Maybe we should interpret that as pointing to this as just a headset.
And if that's the case, then I would say, yeah, wow, evolution actually pointed to space-time as just a headset and don't take it literally.
In which case I would give it a big thumbs up and say,
but it doesn't tell us what's next, right? Just like Einstein doesn't tell us what's outside
space-time. The new physicists are having to make broad and bold leaps outside of space-time. You
have to really go out there. But what you do is you write down your new ideas. And of course,
most of them are not even worth it. Most of them are wrong, but every once in a while, you get a good idea, and then what
you have to do is show that it projects back into space-time and gives you answers that
we can test inside space-time.
So, whatever we come up with outside space-time better project into space-time, and it better
give us Einstein, and it better give us evolution by natural selection as the projection.
If my theory of, so here's how I put it, if my theory of conscious agents outside space-time It better give us Einstein, and it better give us evolution by natural selection as the projection.
So here's how I put it.
If my theory of conscious agents outside space-time, when I project it into space-time, doesn't give me physics, Einstein's physics, quantum theory, and it doesn't give me evolution by natural selection as the projection, then I'm wrong. So evolution is an absolute acid test on my deeper theory.
See, that's how science works.
One more time, one more time, and then I'm going to give up,
because probably we're not going to convince each other.
That very thing you said then,
that my theory had better give me natural selection as a projection,
that's a constraint, it better give me that.
How do you know it had better give you that?
Through using your senses you know through
using your senses uh has obviously given you empirical reason to think your theory had better
give you that as opposed to what the creationist would constrain their theory with and i think if
your if your fitness bits truth argument works you can't trust your senses! And so, yeah, anyway, go on. See, I don't believe evolution. Evolution says that we shouldn't...
No, no, no, but you did... I was focusing on the specific claim you just made.
Right, right. So, evolution... So, all I'm doing as a scientist is I'm just telling you what
this theory entails, and I don't have to believe it. I can say it works over here, and I don't
believe this part of it. So, I'm not caught in my theory. I can say it works over here, and I don't believe this part of it.
So I'm not caught in my theory.
I'm an evaluator of the theory.
And the argument, by the way, is actually quite simple.
There are fitness payoff functions, right? Fitness payoff functions are functions that go from whatever the world is, the state of the world, into the payoffs, say from 0 to 100.
And you can ask a simple technical question.
What is the probability that a generically chosen payoff function would be a homomorphism of any structure in objective reality,
like a total order, a partial order, a metric, whatever it might be, a topology?
And in every case, the answer is precisely zero.
Because for a fitness function to be a homomorphism, it has to satisfy certain equations.
Almost no randomly chosen fitness payoff function will satisfy those equations. It's just that
simple. So, all I have to do is say, look, evolution by natural selection is an incredibly powerful theory, but it entails almost surely, with probability one, that no sensory system has ever evolved to see the truth.
Now, once I've taken that from evolutionary theory, I can say, well, what could that mean?
Well, maybe it can mean that my senses are just a headset, in which case I could be looking beyond this and ask for what's beyond my space-time headset.
Or I could just refuse to believe evolutionary theory on that point.
I myself think evolution might be right.
I don't see the truth, and this is just a headset.
So that's how I go with it. I love evolutionary theory. It says you're not seeing the truth.
I believe it. We're not seeing the truth. It doesn't mean that I'm caught in evolution, because I have this deeper theory that shows that evolution is an artifact, that even time itself is
not an insight into the deeper realm, it's an artifact.
So Philip, why can't Don be saying that Darwinian evolution is some approximation,
it's not exactly correct, there's neo-Darwinism and there's EES, so there are various agglomerations or pieces added to Darwinism afterward. In other words, some biologists
would agree that tradition, the way we traditionally view natural selection, isn't the only mechanism by which we evolve. Okay, so why can't Don say,
hey, look, evolution didn't happen in the exact way that we thought. If it did, then it would
lead to a contradiction. It could happen in some approximate way, and there could be some
underlying mechanisms that are slightly nuanced that produce the wonderful variety we see.
And I also don't know, Don,
if that's what you're saying. I don't mean to speak for you, by the way. I'm just saying,
why can't that be an argument? Well, I suppose in the domain in which we're talking about
our senses and our conscious experience and the apparent design that seems to be in our conscious experience,
we need to appeal, I think, I agree with Richard Dawkins,
we need to appeal to the truth of natural selection
in order to explain that apparent design.
But if this argument works, then we can't do that. We can't, because we can't trust our senses to find out that empirical information that we did evolve through natural selection. So, so the whole thing doesn't get off the ground.
the ground. Don, do you have another analogy other than the supercomputer? Because the computer itself implies computation. Computation implies step-by-step, in which case you can have time.
If we're going to abstract time to say that successive generations can also be time,
then the supercomputer that we could potentially be part of could also have
time in the computational steps. so do you have another analogy
well the the example that's not an analogy but is in fact what we're working on is this
markovian dynamics in which there is no era of time so this is a literal mathematical system
that we're that we're working on right now we published a paper called fusion people want to
see this right it came out in january called fusions of consciousness and and um we actually at the end of the paper raised this issue we point out that
our dynamical systems um don't need to have an arrow of time but then we give the proof we
actually have a three or four line proof that that any projection will give you an arrow of time
from from our system so what we would love to do is to come up with a dynamical system
of conscious agents that projects into space-time. And that's the paper I'm working on right now.
That's exactly what I'm working on today, is that mathematical projection. We're making
really good progress. And my intent is to show, when we get that projection, that we can get evolution by natural selection
in our projected version. So, we'll have a theory in which there are no limited resources,
there are no organisms competing, no nature red in tooth and claw, but when you take this
projection and you lose information, it looks like nature red in tooth and claw. It looks like
there's an arrow of time, and all of that is an artifact of the projection. And I'm saying there's nothing special about this. This is the way science works.
We go from Newton to Einstein. We get Newton as a special case, but there are things Newton can't do,
and there's things that Einstein can explain why you can't do them, but you can do them on Einstein,
and then you see Newton as a projection. When C goes to infinity, you get Newton as a projection. I'll get Darwin, all of evolution by natural selection,
as a projection when I let go of space-time. Can I make one quick physics point? I would say
it's the opposite. I would say that it's with Einstein that you have the limitations. In fact,
with Newton, you can do anything because you can go as fast as you like.
There are no black holes.
It's just Newton can't explain everything, which is different than Newton can't do everything.
By do, I meant explain.
You're absolutely right.
By do, I meant explain.
I mean, I suppose I could put it as a sort of dilemma.
If we're just saying natural selection is not fundamental, you know, that it's just true
in some non-fundamental story of reality, well, then I don't think that gets around Don's argument
because Don's argument isn't saying, you know, appealing to what's self-defeating or not in some
non-fundamental story. But if you say, but if you say no no it's just not really true
it's just not really true well then i'm worried because we need it to be true uh you know to
explain apparent design so either way there's something going wrong here i think that's that's
yeah anyway maybe maybe we should have something else i don't know if we'll make much progress on
this one point and i'm sure there are at least two more points that you all could talk about so yeah i'm going to try my best to rephrase it actually
paraphrase john verveke and i want to see if philip if you agree with this and then we'll see
if we can make headway here but if not then we can move on to something else so john said and it was
either to you don or john said this to bernardo John Vervaeke said, if the level from which we do our science is illusory, then how does that not undermine all the claims of what we're making from that level?
So in other words, if we're claiming science is somehow illusory, but yet we're using science to make that claim, how does that not undermine itself?
So is that what you're saying, Philip, or no?
It sounds related.
Yeah, I mean, I suppose that, again, that's why I suppose my position is a middle way between physicalism and idealism.
I'm a scientific realist, maybe a bit of a structural realist rather than anything more hardcore.
Are you a reductionistist are you both reductionists
i'm less and less reductionist as i get older actually i started off in my academic book
consciousness and fundamental reality really trying to be very reductionist and there are
certain great panpsychist philosophers like luke roloffs who try to be very reductionist. But actually, the more I've talked to neuroscientists
and some condensed matter physicists as well, I just think the reductionist idea is a bit of a
dogma that we don't know anywhere near enough about the brain to know whether everything that goes on in there is totally reducible to underlying chemistry and physics. And you've got interesting views like the assembly theory,'m you know i'm a hardcore realist about physical reality as physicists describe it to us it's there
when we don't look at it but um but it's it's it but but it's that's just mathematical structure
so we need something to fill out that mathematical structure. That's where consciousness comes in. But yeah,
I'm not so persuaded that we need to think that everything that goes on in the brain or in living
systems is just a product of the basic laws of physics. I think that's kind of a dogma that fits
with the zeitgeist at the moment, but it's not actually something empirically proven.
So Don, would you characterize yourself as a reductionist? And by reductionism, I mean that there are individual components that somehow in their interaction give rise to all the complexity
we see. And these components, these are constituent phenomenon that could be something simple like cellular automata or Rubik's cubes or emoticons at the fundament.
And somehow these underrived components spawn everything else.
No. So by reductionism, I would mean that as you go to smaller and smaller scales of space-time, you find more and more fundamental entities and more and more
fundamental laws governing those entities. That's what I take reductionism to be the claim. And I
think that in certain cases, that's been very useful, like in thermodynamics and so forth.
That kind of approach has been very useful. But again, many high-energy theoretical physicists are saying
that reductionism is doomed because the Planck scale is the end of the whole story for smaller
and smaller scales. And if you try to go to even smaller scales, what happens is you get a reversal.
Instead of going to smaller scales, you get bigger and bigger black holes. So, you actually
start going to—so, you get a reversal of thing. So many high energy theoretical physicists are now saying that reductionism is doomed because
space-time is doomed. And I agree. So I'm not a reductionist and it's been useful in certain
aspects of science, but it's not deeply true. What if by reductionism, someone doesn't mean
anything to do with space-time, but just that there are some more simple elements, whether it's cellular automata or Rubik's cubes, that are at the fundament and that breed life when they interact in some other scale, like time or something else,
that everything we see here can be predicted from these tiny elements, these underrived elements.
So what if that's what is meant by reductionism? Are you both reductionists then?
Do you think there's something more than that?
I had a recent article in Scientific American people could look up.
um i had a recent article in scientific american people could look up um uh i think there's a good argument and this is something i explore in the consciousness chapter of the book which is
probably the most challenging chapter of the book it comes with a warning at the start but i think
it's i hope some of the more original bits of the book um i think there's a good challenge to the
reductionism precisely as you just defined it, Kurt.
From the need, we come back to evolution, from the need to make sense of the evolution of biological consciousness. And the thought is that natural selection only cares about behavior,
because it's only behavior that matters for survival. But with the rapid progress in
robotics and AI, I think it's become apparent that you can have incredibly complex information processing and behavioral functioning without any kind of subjective experience at all. survival mechanisms, you know, very complicated mechanisms that can
mechanically track features of their environments and initiate highly survival conducive behavior, but without having any kind of subjective experience at all. I think this is a really
deep challenge. Why did consciousness evolve? Given that complicated mechanisms without consciousness could in principle have survived
just as well.
So I think there's a really deep neglected puzzle here.
And I think part of the solution has to be that consciousness makes a behavioral difference,
that systems with unified consciousness and conscious understanding of the world around them,
that this opens up radically new forms of behavior that are much more conducive to survival than just the forms of mechanistic behavior you just get from building up a mechanism from the laws of physics.
building up a mechanism from the laws of physics.
So that's a sort of argument I try to press from the need to make sense of the evolution of consciousness against the reductionist paradigm.
Don?
Well, so my framework is a little bit different on this point.
So I would say that space-time is just, and the laws of physics are just one particular headset that consciousness can use, one of countless many, and there's nothing particularly interesting
about space-time or special about it.
What's interesting about it is probably it's one of the more trivial data structures that
consciousness can use, not one of the more deep structures.
I can only imagine three-dimensional objects.
I can't even imagine a four-dimensional or five-dimensional object.
And that's a real impediment to a lot of the research I'm doing.
I need to imagine objects that are of much higher dimension.
I can't do it.
I only have three kinds of color receptors.
Mantis shrimps have 10 or 11 or whatever.
In many ways, I feel like my space-time headset is a really—I got a really cheap version of it.
And the laws of physics are really, put it this way, we're not seeing the true causal structure of anything.
In Grand Theft Auto, I mean, I have the appearance of causality.
I turn my steering wheel, my car goes, all this goes down the streets and so forth.
But the appearance of cause and effect in space-time, I would claim, is utterly an illusion.
It's a useful illusion, but it's utterly an illusion, the same illusion as in a VR game.
It looks like the steering wheel turning is causing my car to turn.
Nothing of that sort is happening.
The steering wheel has no causal powers, none.
And there are no causal powers inside space-time whatsoever.
And there are no causal powers inside space-time whatsoever.
So you can see my framework is entirely different.
But what I have to do is then show, who am I then that's doing this?
I'm not an object in space-time.
I'm not a small consciousness inside space-time.
And I didn't ultimately evolve inside space-time. Space-time, I'm not in space-time.
Space-time is in me. Space-time is a little data structure in me, and it's not the only one that
I could possibly use. So it's a complete reversal of the whole picture. What I meant by reductionism
doesn't have to have causation. I just mean that you can understand the whole by analyzing its constituent parts.
Okay.
If that's the definition of reductionism, do you still subscribe to it or you don't subscribe to it?
Well, again, if you think about the headset approach, ultimately when you look at smaller and smaller scales inside the headset or parts, you get down to pixels. And in some sense, you don't really explain anything.
I mean, my steering wheel can't be explained by the pixels out of which it's made, right?
It's just not going to explain that. So, ultimately is only a projection of the truth.
It's never the truth.
It's a very limited, so no scientific theory can ever be a theory of everything.
And every scientific theory will automatically have its necessary limits.
And ultimately, my feeling is that
every scientific theory,
my own included,
scratch probability zero depths
of reality.
In other words, reality,
whatever it is,
will infinitely,
infinitely transcend
any scientific theory's attempts
to explain it.
And that's just the way it, you. And that's just the way it is.
So there will never be a theory of everything.
And the simple argument for that is, look, every scientific theory makes assumptions.
Those assumptions are the miracles of the theory, right?
You're not explaining those assumptions.
You're assuming them.
You can say, well, I can get you a deeper theory that explains those assumptions.
You can't.
Your deeper theory will have its own assumptions.
And this goes on ad infinitum.
Ad infinitum.
And that means that we're infinitely far.
Right now, we're infinitely far from a theory of everything, and we will always be infinitely far from a theory of everything.
And that includes Hoffman's theory is infinitely far from a theory of everything.
So, deep humility is required at every step in our scientific theory building.
Very, very deep humility.
And it raises the question, who am I?
Who am I that I transcend space-time?
Space-time is a little data structure in me.
I'm not a little object in space-time.
Space-time is a little data structure that I use, and it's one of many that I could use. Who am I that is doing this? It raises a very, very deep question. In that sense,
I take the idea that consciousness is fundamental very, very seriously, that it transcends space-time
completely. Space-time is trivial. It's a non-entity compared to the depth
of consciousness. It's a complete non-entity
in terms of its complexity.
We transcend it. Whatever we are
completely transcends it.
And when we
die, we'll just drop that headset
and we'll find out who we are.
Is it time to talk about the meaning of life?
I think it's getting deep.
The other part of your book.
Right, the other part of your book. What is the meaning of life i think it's getting deep the other part of your book right
the other part of your book what is the meaning of life philip um yeah so but you know most of this
most of this book is is just a sort of cold-blooded scientific and philosophical argument for
cosmic purpose arguing that there is reason to take seriously
this idea of goal-directedness at the fundamental level of reality. Weird as it sounds, I just think
that's where the evidence is pointing to, and we have to face up to that. I annoy people on
Twitter by suggesting that Bertrand Russell would have believed in cosmic purpose,
because he followed the evidence where it led, but it just wasn't there when he was alive. But so, so yeah, most of the argument
is that just cold-blooded case for that. But I suppose in the first and last chapters,
I'm thinking about the implications for human existence. And yeah, I don't, so I don't want
to be kind of too dogmatic about what is the
single way of living a meaningful life. Um, you know, I suppose I'm interested in
suggesting options that are maybe different from the familiar options of
traditional religion on the one hand and secular atheism on the other. Um, but yeah, overall, I think there's a, there's a defender kind of middle way ground here,
really. On the one hand, you get some religious philosophers like William Lane Craig who say,
you know, if there's no point to the universe, it's all pointless. You know, we might as well
just rape and kill each other. You know, it's all totally pointless and meaningless. The other extreme, you get, you know, the familiar secular atheist position that probably and so on. But if there is a purpose to the whole of reality, then maybe there's a potential for our lives to be more meaningful. You know, if you can contribute in some small way to the purposes of the whole of reality, that's huge. You know, we want our
lives to make a difference. That's about as big a difference as you could imagine making. So yeah.
And just finally, I suppose, you know, just speaking for myself, I feel starting to live
as a cosmic purposivist, you know, living in hope that there's a greater purpose to what's going on here.
A cosmic what?
Purposivist. Cosmic purposivist.
Ah, I see, I see.
Sort of living in hope of a greater purpose to what's going on.
I have found to be a deeply kind of meaningful form of living. I think most of all,
I think it has brought me a sense of, a deep sense of peace in some way. I was talking to my wife
about this just this week. Because I guess I'm quite kind of career driven. I think I hope partly
through pure motives, you know, like I really believe in the things I'm arguing for and I want
to persuade the world. Probably there's a bit of ego there as well, you know,
I want to kind of make my mark or whatever. But I found that cosmic purposivism has
made me less bothered about those things, not because I don't think they're important,
but because I'm conceiving of them as part of some much bigger thing that's going on that I'm
inevitably just a tiny part of. And hence my task is just, you know, to do the best I can to
contribute to this much bigger thing going on. And conceiving of those, conceiving of things in
that way, I suppose, makes me less bothered about my own personal successes and failures and frees me up to enjoy life a little bit more, enjoy playing in the snow as I was with my family this weekend.
Not that I wasn't happy before, but maybe bought a deeper sense of happiness.
So, yeah, so I suppose I'm just trying to suggest options that aren't the familiar options for thinking about the meaning of life. Okay. How do you argue that, by the way?
So you just outlined some views, but how do you argue that those views are correct?
Well, that's, I guess, going back to the starting point. So part of it is
the fine-tuning of physics for life, i think just in our standard bayesian way of
thinking about things just is evidence that there is some kind of goal-directedness towards life
in the very early stages of the universe um and i think we're sort of in denial about that because
it just doesn't fit with how we've got used to thinking about science. As I said, I used to think the multiverse option
was the obviously more plausible option for a long time. Cosmic purpose sounded very silly to me,
but I've been persuaded that there's some dodgy reasoning going on in trying to explain fine
tuning in terms of the multiverse. I could talk about that if you want um yeah and um well also
the kind of arguments about making sense of the evolution of consciousness that we
started talking about then so it's those two things i think making sense of the emergence
of conscious understanding which i think belies our current scientific paradigm and and the fine-tuning of
physics for life most people think oh well god is the alternative but i think there's a middle
ground a neglected middle ground here between the traditional atheist picture of a meaningless
purposeless universe and the traditional western god on the other hand don what is the meaning of
life to you and feel free to comment
on anything that philip has just said well i first on the point of agreement i think that um
i believe in a version of purpose of conscious purpose this purpose of, whatever the word was. So I think it's not the standard physicalist framework that we're nature, red and tooth and claw, and there's really no meaning of purpose, and it's pointless.
I think that that's just taking the headset literally when we shouldn't take the headset literally as the final word.
My own view on purpose is, and comes with who I think we are.
So I don't think I'm a 160-pound object in space-time.
I think that space-time is a tiny data structure inside me and inside you.
I think that I am, and you are, consciousness that transcends any scientific theory,
that I am the deep reality and you are the deep reality of consciousness.
You are that consciousness.
And in fact, there's only one.
So in fact, my view is that right now, consciousness in a Hoffman avatar,
a Philip Goff avatar, and a Kurt avatar is talking to itself,
the one
infinite consciousness. And what it's doing is finding out about itself. In some sense,
the infinite consciousness knows itself by knowing what it's not. It plunges itself into
this little headset, loses itself, thinks it's a little object in space-time, and then slowly wakes up and realizes,
no, I transcend this headset.
And that's how it knows what it is,
by knowing with countless headsets what it's not.
So the purpose is, from my point of view,
is consciousness is here to know itself by waking up to what it's not.
And the fundamental thing that comes out of this is that, you know, some religions say,
love your neighbor as yourself, but I'm saying your neighbor is yourself. And that is the
foundation for true love, is to recognize that that's just me under a different avatar.
Even my cat is me under a different avatar.
And so from this point of view, the whole purpose of life is I'm this infinite consciousness that is finding out who I am.
And it's a theorem that it'll never be done. It's a mathematical theorem that no system can ever truly know itself
because in the very act of knowing yourself,
you build a model of yourself and you become more complicated.
So now you have to get a new model of yourself
with the more complicated model and so forth.
So this is the one consciousness, the infinite consciousness,
posing as a philosopher, as a scientist, as a podcast interviewer, and learning about itself and waking up.
And eventually it takes off this headset and tries on a less cheap headset than this one.
And goes through the same process in a different way.
So that's sort of my guess about what it is.
Can I just add something to that? I mean, I guess it's another
point in which I value Don's work and in which we're trying to do something similar that
I think there's a huge demographic, a huge proportion of the population
that identify as spiritual but not religious. But in general, academics don't cater for that group. In academic philosophy,
I would say most people are secular atheists. There's some really good quality philosophy of
religion, but it tends to be very traditional Christians, a few Jews. There's one very good
Muslim philosopher of religion that's in the analytic tradition that's emerged recently.
religion that's in in the analytic tradition that's emerged recently um and then i think from that we get this perception that spiritual but not religious is fluffy thinking and not very
thought through but i think that's just the contingent circumstances that you know academics
haven't put rigorous work into developing philosophically scientifically supported
options here so this is one thing i'm trying to do with this book. And I've got a three-year Templeton project on trying to work out if the universe
is conscious, that's kind of related to this stuff that funded this conference that Don came to,
where I debated Sean Carroll on whether consciousness is fundamental. People can
check out on YouTube if they're interested in. But yeah, so I think that's very exciting that
this whole new, I mean, it's always been there to an extent, but it's connecting up this whole new kind of academic area of trying to make rigorous sense of between traditional religion and secular atheism.
And just, you know, expanding the debate is always really interesting and adds new challenges.
is always really interesting and adds new challenges.
Although I don't like this idea that we're all the same person.
I guess I'm a little bit more Western in my thinking than Eastern on this regard. I sort of feel like the value of love and self-sacrifice is that you're not me
and I'm still sacrificing myself for someone that's not me,
that's the other. And I find that's what's beautiful about love. And when it's like,
oh no, it's just me. It's all me. I sort of, that kind of depresses me.
Then it's masturbation.
Yeah. Sex is just masturbation. I hadn't thought of it. That makes it even worse now you put it
that way. But I mean, that's not an argument. That's not an argument. That's just a sort of gut
ethical, primal ethical response.
Many of these claims come down to gut intuitions. So Don, I'm curious about the neurons not
existing, but the cat existing. So the cat is an avatar that has its own perspective.
Then if we were to scale that down into the perspective of a neuron, then does a neuron
still technically exist if you're not there because the neuron has its own headset or even let's just say the cat
well yeah or the or the cat right so ultimately um it's consciousness looking at itself through
a headset and and so it sometimes it sees itself um So what does a headset do?
A headset dumbs things down, right?
That's what a headset does.
It deletes lots of information.
So from this point of view, I should be very, very clear.
The distinction that we make between living and non-living things is not principled.
And the distinction between conscious and unconscious objects is not a principled distinction,
in my point of view.
So right now I'm looking at you guys on a video screen,
and I see pixels of Kurt's face and Philip's face
and so forth, but I also see pixels of the background,
like of the walls and so forth.
Now, some of the pixels are giving me insight
about Philip's and Kurt's consciousness,
and others are giving me nothing on the wall. Now, do I want to say that certain pixels
are conscious? These are the conscious pixels, and those are the unconscious pixels?
No, that's dumb. Pixels are just pixels. From this point of view in which space-time is just
a headset, the distinction we make between living things like cats and non-living things like rocks is entirely an artifact of the limits of our headset.
I'm always interacting with consciousness.
Always.
And I'm always interacting with an equally complicated one infinite consciousness.
I'm always interacting with that.
So there's not like stupid consciousnesses.
No, I'm always interacting with the. So, there's not like stupid consciousnesses. No, I'm always interacting
with the one infinite consciousness. But my interface, because it's an interface,
dumbs things down. So, when I'm interacting with the cat, I'm interacting, I am this one
consciousness interacting with itself through a headset and looking at itself. So, I'm getting
a cat image of myself and or
a bacterium image of myself, whatever it might be. These are all perspectives of myself. They're not,
they're just perspectives. They're not the truth, but I'm always interacting with the one
infinite consciousness. Now, in the paper that we're about to write on this, we actually have an idea about how to talk about the one.
We found a partial order on consciousnesses.
So it's a mathematical structure.
It's a non-Boolean order on consciousnesses.
It's a completely mathematically rigorous thing.
So it turns out it's non-Boolean, and there's no ultimate top to the one.
So when I talk about the one, typically we think there's some guy at the top or something like that.
No, this is, the mathematics of this is far more complicated.
It's a completely non-Boolean structure.
And so when I talk about the one, I haven't wrapped my head around conceptually what that could possibly be.
It's too complicated.
Also, to wrap your head around it, you'd have to go all the way up Cantor's
hierarchy and beyond Cantor's hierarchy. So, this is a partial order that goes all the way up
Cantor's hierarchy and so forth. So, when I talk about the one, it's not a trivial thing.
The mathematics is complicated, and I'm sure this complicated mathematics is trivial compared to the structure of the one.
So, whatever this one is, it's truly impressive.
And it's looking at itself through cats and rocks and so forth.
But I'll just repeat again.
The distinction between living and nonliving is not principled.
There's no deep distinction there.
And the distinction between conscious and unconscious is not principled. There's no deep distinction there. And the distinction between conscious
and unconscious is not principled. All of them are artifacts of the limitations of our headset,
and nothing deeper than that. I think we're probably coming back to some agreement again
with the distinction between living and non-living, conscious and non-conscious.
I'd like to ask Don, I don't know whether we're running out of time, what you think
about the fine-tuning of physics for life.
But before I do that, actually,
Kurt, would it be alright to say
what's wrong with the multiverse?
Would that be permissible?
Sure.
I'm really excited about this, actually,
because this has been an argument
that's been in the academic journals
about probability for decades,
since 1982. But in a typical case of academics talking to themselves, nobody knows about it
outside of academic philosophy, despite huge interest in fine-tuning and some physicists
arguing for the multiverse, some theists arguing for God and so on.
So I'm really excited to get it out to a broader audience. So yeah, the basic claim is that
the inference from fine-tuning to a multiverse commits the inverse gambler's fallacy,
right? So suppose Don and I go to a casino tonight and we walk in and the first thing we go into a small room and we see someone.
What? There's just one guy having this incredible run of luck at roulette, just winning and winning and winning. And, you know, I turn to Don and say, wow, the casino must be full tonight.
And Don says, what are you talking about?
We've just seen this one guy. And I say, well, you know, if there are tens of thousands of people
playing roulette in the casino, then it's not so surprising that someone's going to have an
incredible run of luck. And that's just what we've observed, someone having an incredible run of luck.
Now, everyone agrees that's a fallacy, right? Our observational evidence is just this one individual having an incredible run of luck. And no matter
how many people are playing roulette in other rooms in the casino, it has no bearing on the
likelihood of this one particular person we've observed. It's related to the more familiar
gambler's fallacy. You know, you think, oh, I've had a terrible look all night, I'm bound to win big now. So everyone agrees that's a fallacy, but it looks, to my mind,
indiscernible to the reasoning of the multiverse theorist, at least if they're arguing from fine
tuning. You know, you look around and think, oh my God, the numbers in physics are just right for
life. There must be loads of other universes with terrible numbers, right? Well, our observational
evidence is just this one universe we've observed. No matter how many other universes there are,
has no bearing on the likelihood of this one universe we've observed getting the right
numbers. It's just like postulating other people playing casino elsewhere, sorry, other people
playing roulette elsewhere in the casino to explain the one individual we've observed.
people playing roulette elsewhere in the casino to explain the one individual we've observed um now there are all sorts of i mean there's the anthropic principle people bring up um
there's the scientific case for the multiverse well actually i'm also excited that
even though this is this particular objection to the multiverse has been discussed for decades in
the journals no one's connected it to the to the actual scientific discussion based in inflationary cosmology of the multiverse. So that's what I try
to do in the book. So I think, yeah, even once you take into account the anthropic principle
and the scientific evidence for eternal inflation and so on, I still think the basic problem
survives, that it's just demonstrably fallacious reasoning.
And so we're stuck with cosmic purpose.
So what if someone says, well, it's not a fallacy because in that example with observing
the person winning over and over, you could potentially see other people not winning.
Whereas in the case of the fine-tuning
of the universe, a better analogy would be that we're in the office where people come in to get
their check for winning the lottery. And we keep seeing people there and we're like, oh, everyone's
winning the lottery. Yeah, but you're only able to see the people who are winning the lottery.
So that would be the better analogy.
Good, good. Yes. So that's, yeah, that's kind of appealing to the anthropic principle.
Good, good. Yes. So that's, yeah, that's kind of appealing to the anthropic principle. Well, two things. I mean, one, we could just add to the analogy, right? Suppose there's a sniper at the back of the room waiting to blow our brains out as we walk in, if the first person isn't winning big, right? And so we create a kind of artificial selection effect. So now it's just like real world fine tuning, right? In that scenario, the only thing we were
able to observe is someone winning big, but that still doesn't mean the fallacy goes away.
But at a deeper level, I think, and this is what I go into in the book, we know what's going on
behind this fallacy. It's rooted in a very important principle in
probabilistic reasoning called the requirement of total evidence, which is the principle that
you're obliged to always work with the most specific evidence you have. So suppose, you know,
Don's on trial for murder and, you know, the jury, sorry, the prosecution says to the jury, Don always carries a knife around with him. When the reality of the situation is Don always carries a butter knife around with him.
led them by not giving the most specific information we have, which is not just that he carries a knife, but that he carries specifically a butter knife. So this is a
very important, well-accepted principle. This is what the multiverse theorist violates because they
construe that the evidence of fine-tuning is some universe is fine-tuned, right? And then that's
made more likely by a multiverse. But we had more specific evidence than that namely that this universe is
fine-tuned um just like in the casino case our more specific evidence is this person has um
played well and then we're obliged by this principle to work with that more specific evidence
and once we do then a multiverse is not going to explain fine tuning. I mean, maybe I could just, I've talked a lot already, but the case you give is what, well, Roger White, who wrote the classic paper on this in the year 2000, it's well, we're going to observe them, right?
So that's like, with the real world selection effect, the real world selection effect is that
if we exist, the universe must be fine-tuned, but it's not the other way around. It's not if
there's a fine-tuned universe, we're going to be in it. That's the converse selection effect. So White makes that clear with a sort of sci-fi analogy.
Imagine we were once disembodied spirits floating through the multiverse looking for a fine-tuned
universe. And if once we find a fine-tuned universe, we go into it. In that case, there'll
be a converse selection effect, right? Not only if we exist,
then the universe is fine-tuned, but if there's a fine-tuned universe, we're going to exist and be
in it, right? So that's a converse selection effect, and that's what's modelled in the very
example you gave. If someone plays well, we're going to observe them, but that's not the real
world selection effect. The real world selection effect is captured by my sniper example. As you see, that doesn't remove the fallacy. Sorry, that was very long-winded, but it's a big and fascinating discussion.
The one consciousness is fundamental.
This infinite, unbounded consciousness that you and I are is fundamental.
And space-time is just a headset, one of countless headsets that it's using to look at itself.
So when it projects itself, it is life itself.
And when it projects itself, the projection, sometimes parts of the projection make clear what is living and sometimes it doesn't, right?
Sometimes things look like rocks.
Sometimes things look like living organisms.
And there's an arrow of time that's part of the projection.
There is no time in the one of a big bang, an arrow of time, an evolution from less complicated to more
complicated things, all of that is an artifact of the headset. The fundamental reality is this
infinite life, infinite consciousness, looking at itself through a headset. And so, the reason why
there's the appearance of fine-tuning is because the universe is nothing but a headset of an already existing living thing that's looking at itself through the headset.
So a consistent projection will be consistent with life.
Can I just interrupt?
Sorry, the discussion is just getting interesting, but my little six-year-old daughter has just come in, and it's quarter to one one and i think i might have to read to her to
get her back to sleep so unfortunately we have to put a pin in that i think that's no problem it was
a pleasure and i hope to host you both on again either together or individually thank you so much
for coming on thank you both always a pleasure kurt and Kurt and Philip. Thanks, Don. Always so stimulating. And thanks, Kurt, for probing questions and for hosting us.
The links to what everyone has mentioned, whether it's a debate between Philip and Don on Philip's
channel, or whether it's the books of Don or of Philip or articles will be in the description.
All right. Thank you all for coming.
A baddash, guys. Thanks so much.
Thank you.
Okay. Take care. Take care.
Bye-bye.
All right, if you enjoyed that episode, then I recommend watching the Donald Hoffman episode
with Josje Bak. That was another theolocution. There's another one with Donald Hoffman and
John Vervaeke. There's a solo Donald Hoffman. That is where we go into the technical details
of his fusions paper and the interface theory ofception, as well as Philip Goff will likely be coming on one-on-one,
and most likely there will be a part two to this
with Donald Hoffman and Philip Goff.
So again, if you have any questions,
leave them in the format query in the comment section below
so that I can pose it to them, citing your name.
If you'd like to see these podcasts happen with more frequency
and even greater depth,
then consider donating at patreon.com slash kurtjaimungal.
That's C-U-R-T-J-A-I-M-U-N-G-A-L.
We've been having a significant problem
getting sponsors for this channel with monetizing,
and that's a large part,
a large, large part of any creator on YouTube.
It may seem like this channel's this huge success,
but it's decidedly not in the financial domain.
And so your donations help tremendously,
especially if you do it over
PayPal, where the creator takes more of a cut, and even more especially if you do it monthly over
PayPal. But again, whatever you like, whatever you're comfortable with. My wife and I both thank
you. The editor thanks you. And anyhow, welcome to the new year. There are several large plans
for Theories of Everything. Can't wait to announce them. Thank you. for Theories of Everything, where people explicate toes, disagree respectfully about theories, and
build as a community our own toes. Links to both are in the description. Also, I recently found out
that external links count plenty toward the algorithm, which means that when you share on
Twitter, on Facebook, on Reddit, etc., it shows YouTube that people are talking about this outside
of YouTube, which in turn greatly aids the distribution on YouTube as well.
Last but not least, you should know that this podcast is on iTunes.
It's on Spotify. It's on every one of the audio platforms.
Just type in Theories of Everything and you'll find it.
Often I gain from re-watching lectures and podcasts, and I read that in the comments.
Hey, total listeners also gain from replaying.
So how about instead re-listening on those platforms?
iTunes, Spotify, Google Podcasts,
whichever podcast catcher you use.
If you'd like to support more conversations like this,
then do consider visiting patreon.com slash kurtjaimungal
and donating with whatever you like.
Again, it's support from the sponsors and you
that allow me to work on Toe full-time.
You get early access to ad-free audio episodes there as well. For instance, this episode was released
a few days earlier. Every dollar helps far more than you think. Either way, your viewership is
generosity enough. you